On politics, law and ideology

On politics, law and ideology



Today nothing is more modern than the onslaught against the political…. There must no longer be political problems, only organizational technical and economic-sociological ones.


(Carl Schmitt, Political Theology, 2005a: 65)



Would the grand ‘world police intervention’, which NATO conducts in the name of world-civil-society then boil down to an ordinary war, indeed a dirty war, that only brought even greater suffering to the Balkans? Wouldn’t that also mean to put wind into the sails of Carl Schmitt, who apparently always knew better: ‘Whoever uses the term humanity wants to betray’? Schmitt expressed his anti-humanism in the famous formula of: ‘Humanity, bestiality’. The nagging doubt whether legal pacifism is itself in the end the wrong bet, is the most disturbing of the sources of disquiet.


(Jürgen Habermas, ‘Bestiality and Humanity: A war on the border between law and morality’, 1999)5


This chapter addresses the significance of the key terms and ideas of its title for a Schmittian theory of modern law, starting with that of ‘politics’ or, more precisely, the mediation of law by ‘the political’. However, the bulk of this chapter will address the related theme of law as including an ideological dimension, in particular how the ideologies of liberal constitutionalism project a depoliticised model of ‘legality’. Schmitt claims that, whenever it is subject to closer and more critical examination, the apparent coherence of this model unravels into a series of difficulties and contradictions. In addition, the question arises as to whether liberal ideologies project an unduly narrow conception of law, and hence legal scholarship. Does this model fail to recognise not only the essentially interpretative nature of the legal enterprise, but also the need for scholars to develop a wider and more contextual form of analysis? Do such ideologies generally exaggerate the ‘determinacy’ of legal norms, at the expense of a realistic grasp of the crucial and inevitable role of discretion within the legal process, including the question of who decides and upon what concrete basis? If we can identify such distortions, then what are their implications for liberalism’s ideological interpretation of the nature of the judicial role and, in particular, the remarkably ideological politics of depoliticising the role of judges? Indeed, can a suitably critical interpretation of these particular ideological projections of the nature of law and the legal process expose more general contradictions in such ‘depoliticisation agendas’ – including within their specifically ‘jurisprudential’ expressions, such as Kelsenian legal positivism?


Schmitt extended his critique of liberal constitutional ideologies to include the related topic of the operation of ‘liberal cosmopolitan’ ideologies and the ‘ideology of humanity’ within international law as distinct variants upon liberalism more generally (Zolo 2002). Finally, it may prove useful to briefly outline Schmitt’s distinctly illiberal and broadly Hobbesian model of law as an expression of power and authority. Is this able to retrieve a number of the material and socio-legal dimensions that liberal ideologies typically need to exclude precisely in order to vindicate, and then give a spurious impression of legitimacy for, their own approach? Will the distinctly ideological nature of liberal projections become clearer if we view them from the alternative perspective of a Schmittian model of law?


The concept of ‘strategic myth’, which constitutes a major theme for the second half of this work, will be clarified in a later section devoted to this topic.


The politics of law and the law of politics


How are the expressions ‘politics’ and ‘law’ of this book’s title best interpreted in this context? Perhaps, they are best understood as discrete and mutually exclusive fields, or as mutually dependent practices?


Politics can be usefully thought of in Schmittian terms not as a given ‘domain’ – akin to the distinct realms of literature, industry or education. Instead, it signals an ever-present possibility for conflicts to arise in any sphere in which the participants’ sense of positive association and disassociation intensify to the point where – in relation to a disputed issue – they regroup into polarised ‘us’ versus ‘them’ factions (Schmitt 1996a: 26–37). This is an expressly ‘formal’ and descriptive-analytical definition (lacking any overt moral prescriptions as to how political formations ought to mobilise in pursuit of which concrete goals). As such, it is not to be confused with either a concrete judgement in favour of the specific politics of imperialism and militarism, or with pacifism or other ‘social ideals’ (Schmitt 1996a: 54). Indeed, later we will see how Schmitt expressly attacks the deceptions and self-deceptions involved in ideological depoliticisation, including that exhibited by the ‘ideology of humanity’. However, his definition of the political does not offer extrinsic and substantive moral criteria for affirming any specific values as ‘worthy goals’ for a progressive political struggle and crusade, whilst negating others as inauthentic or regressive. Indeed, he expressly distinguishes his definition from an earlier militaristic substantive conception of Erich Kaufmann (Schmitt 1996: 33 n 12, 55).


Schmitt defines political activity as an emerging product of a polarisation around relations of group affinity, neutrality and hostility. In ‘exceptional’ moments of perceived national crisis, the sovereignty of the state becomes emphatically present by the executive seeking to mobilise citizens against a ‘public enemy’ identified and named as such by these leaders (Schmitt 1996a; Schmitt 2005a: 6, 13). Politics is a public and collective phenomenon, not to be confused with purely interpersonal animosities and conflict between private individuals for example. In this sense, even religions with universalistic and otherworldly aspirations, such as Christianity, can become emphatically political whenever theological-doctrinal differences lead, for instance, to schisms, sectarian conflicts, inquisitions, religious-creedal wars, contested reformations etc. By the same token, economic life becomes intensely political whenever it results in the formation of opposed social classes consciously engaged in a type of class conflict where one party identifies itself as ‘oppressed’ and/or ‘exploited’ by the other, and therefore seeks revolutionary social transformation through a general strike or other insurrectionary form of direct action (Schmitt 1988: ch 4).


A Schmittian approach to law is committed to the idea that being human involves immersion in ever-present possibilities for collective conflict arising from virtually every conceivable form of social activity. Politics remains a basic concept of human anthropology because we are primarily political animals for whom the unrealistic prospect of the entire disappearance of the political would entail drastic, if perhaps ‘comfortable’, dehumanisation. Whilst political activity endures over time, specific political formations, such as that centred on the medieval or modern state, remain contingent and vulnerable to collapse. Every overtly political phenomenon, including law, can be challenged through effective depoliticisation and apparent neutralisation of conflicts. If successful, these tendencies at least partly deprive the presence of law of its specific political character. Because programmes of depoliticisation, which often take the form of liberal ideological reductions of issues to either ethics or economics, are themselves polemical movements, they remain trapped in – and ironically exhibit – the logic of the political itself. Depoliticisation of law can thus be subjected to the same ironic blowback-reversal as a ‘war to end all wars’, or efforts to end cannibalism by eating the last cannibal.


For Schmitt, a key achievement of early modernity within Europe was to displace the power of the medieval Church by securing a form of national sovereignty involving a political-legislative monopoly. That is, an exclusive authority to enact laws defining the nation’s principles, values and ideals – including those for whom citizens can be conscripted into military service to fight for and defend. Faced with external or internal threats to a nation’s way of life, citizens typically look to the state, not paramilitary militias or private corporations for example, to safeguard their security. This hard-won monopoly remains at risk from contestation by imperialistic foreign powers, revolutionary groups deploying partisan warfare, and international terrorism. Each of these can be expected to seek to capture state power in the name of a supposedly higher secular or religious principle of legitimacy. The modern state can expressly contest such movements forcefully, and/or seek to ‘buy off’ or redirect their demands through a variety of policy measures, including welfare state initiatives, the encouragement of depoliticising models of group self-identity and anti-terrorism strategies (Schmitt 1996a; Schmitt 2007).


Depoliticisation strategies can include the promotion of idealistic pacifist ideologies. Typically, these reject the possibility of identifying public enemies because, to the delight of a nation’s real enemies, ultimately nothing is deemed sufficiently meaningful and valuable to defend through the mobilisation of military force, not even pacifist ideals. By contrast, the modern state cannot renounce politics or project the possibility of its dissolution in favour of a communist utopia involving the ‘withering away of law’ and the mere ‘administration of things’. Instead, the logic of the political dictates that it must seek to deploy sovereign power to preserve an effective system of criminal law, together with a police, security and military service capable of preventing state power being seized by such designated enemies, whether these are domestic or international.


The point concerning politics interpreted as the relative degree of intensity of friend and enemy distinctions and oppositions, applies to all distinctive spheres of civil society. Within the legal sphere, this includes testcase litigation in which, for example, victims of defective medicine bring a case against a combination of drug companies and their regulators, law reform controversies where rival social groups take diametrically opposed positions, and even the frequently factionalised internal politics of law schools and academic conferences. Here, individuals meet but frameworks of ideas and assumptions often fail to enter into any meaningful or mutually enriching dialogue.


Recent historical experience makes it clear that promoters of rival ideological agendas may seek to obtain government power directly (or indirectly through sponsorship of political parties) in order, for example, to either optimise or minimise the scope of ‘private enterprise’. Whichever side emerges triumphant during the resulting ideological conflict will typically promote a legislative programme that gives some – albeit often diluted – effect to its distinctive ideological ‘vision’, to the realisation of its mythic beliefs disguised as self-evident truths. In this respect, debates over law reform can also take shape as distinctly political debates as to what ought to count as ‘the way forward’ in terms of public policy and the attempted ‘steering’ of society more generally.


Equally, specific legal devices, such as judicial review and human rights remedies, provide judges with restricted opportunities for striking down government decisions and entire policies, even in fields such as counter-terrorism and other areas where they are fulfilling specific election pledges. Where this takes place, even on purely technical and procedural grounds that appear politically neutral, the judges will inevitably be accused of engaging in a one-sided form of political partisanship. Judges who overtly change the meaning or scope of a legal doctrine on policy grounds will risk charges of usurping the political role of the legislature. And yet it is widely recognised that the distinction between the faithful application of law and judicial law-making is a hard one to make in practice. This is because application presupposes reinterpretation, and the latter is – to a greater or lesser extent – inevitably selective involving value-driven choices between alternatives.


‘Politics’ also arises within the legal field between judges who follow the tradition of conservative-statist deference to government claims relating to claimed national security imperatives, and others who take the more liberal constitutionalist stance of human rights fundamentalism.6 This second grouping amongst the senior judiciary are concerned to hold government ministers to account by insisting that they must clearly demonstrate the existence not only of valid legal grounds for their determinations of national security, but also that all resulting decisions avoid appearing either discriminatory or disproportionate.7 In such contexts, there is a political conflict of orientation which leads, over time, to a reversal of previously dominant judicial orientations. These become transformed incrementally as such ultra-liberal alternatives come to make their presence felt within the highest courts. Such instances of institutional politics within law need to be understood as an extended war for supremacy between contrasting ideological orientations with a range of cases amounting to specific battles. Given that 19th- and even 18th-century cases can still serve as contemporary precedents, the politics involved in the overcoming and displacement of one judicial orientation by another is often a drawn out process of gradual and cross – as well as intra-generational – change, in which the conflictual-political dimension is rarely openly acknowledged. However, a covert form of conflict between divergent judicial orientations, understood as rival ideologies, is at least as political as any overt and widely acknowledged one.


Where it is not possible to identify actual or at least potential friend/enemy groupings amongst the judiciary, the legal profession more generally, or between different branches of state involved in the separation of powers, then politics within the legal sphere continues to exist. However, it endures in a state of latency or dormancy (Schmitt 1999).


In short, the inclusion of ‘politics’ in my book title refers to the various ways in which our experience of law shows that it is implicated in real or potentially conflictual situations in any field of social action to which it could be applied, including interstate relations. Furthermore, the invariant defining quality of politics is a form of association/disassociation sufficient to generate the differentiation of ‘friends’ from both ‘enemies’ and ‘neutrals’.


On this Schmittian definition of politics, it is possible to imagine – but perhaps only imagine – a utopian global situation of a unified ‘humanity-at-large’ governed by a universally accepted world government of uncontested legitimacy, and free of all polarised oppositions and ‘us versus them’ relations. That is, a totally depoliticised and neutralised context where, for example, international criminal law, war crimes trials and humanitarian law would have become anachronistic, a mere reminder of times past. However, the world in which we now wake up to every morning shows little signs of even approximating this redemptive pipe dream of a secularised heaven on earth, the opium-fantasy of liberal cosmopolitanism all too often deployed as a moralistic benchmark to slander the politics of existing institutional practices of nation states.


Another decisive area of the politics of law concerns the all too relevant question of the public law practice of declaring a ‘state of emergency’, which Schmitt analyses in Political Theology for example (Schmitt 2005a). The very process of coming to a definition of this term is complex. It is situated at the limit and intersection of both the norms of public law doctrine and ‘exceptional’ political events that characterise the factual side of the state of emergency (Schmitt 2005a: 6, 13). The latter must, it seems, be interpreted through the field of politics, rather than through those of public law. Hence, the necessary effort of public lawyers to come to terms with emergency powers laws remains caught in the contradiction of analysing ‘legal measures’ that cannot themselves be fully understood from a ‘strictly legal’ orientation. This field of scholarship has to address a state of emergency through its distinctive framework(s), whilst recognising that this typically exhibits a legal form of something essentially political and lacking intrinsic legal form. Such analysis often finds itself transported through law to something extra-legal but nevertheless included uneasily within legal discourse.


Furthermore, this is a field in which law authorises the suspension of its exercise, and in theorising this we are confronted with the instructive mediation and overpowering of such legal measures by real-life events, whose significance is irreducible to their legal meaning and implications. Here, an apparent or presumed difference arises between public law measures and emphatically political realities that embrace terrorism, civil war, revolutionary insurrection and mass civil disobedience or – in Schmittian terminology – ‘the right to resist’. Public law has to answer the question of whether the dictatorial mode of governance authorised by law-suspending emergency powers legislation has remained an exceptional response to extraordinary events predestined to end once the ‘normal situation’ has been restored (Schmitt 2005a: 6, 13)? Alternatively, has it become extended or ‘normalised’ as a ‘sovereign’ form of dictatorship? Answering this question, which Giorgio Agamben has explored, requires reflections that are as much political as legal. In short, the effort of public lawyers to interpret emergency powers measures brings home both the relative difference between law and politics as well as their deeper and inescapable bond.


Law as an ideological practice involving depoliticisation


It is reasonable to expect a book about Schmittian legal theory entitled Law as Ideology, Politics and Strategic Myth to include a section on that aspect of legal experience which can be usefully identified as ‘ideological’ in some, as yet unclarified, sense of this difficult concept. However, Schmitt does not provide an express and general ‘theory of ideology’. What his writings do offer, however, is a fairly detailed and critical account of the qualities and operation of liberal ideologies of legality, together with an equally critical, even polemical, account of the ‘ideology of humanity’. The latter, he claims, is focused primarily upon the discourse of a form of international law decisively shaped by the victors of the 20th century world wars, particularly the United States.


The technocratic activity of interpreting law and politics as mutually exclusive, of treating the realm of politics as diametrically opposed to that of ‘law’ (narrowly defined), and interpreting the former as a contaminating influence that allegedly pollutes ‘strict legal analysis’ or rule-based (or ‘normativist’) forms of judicial decision-making, will be termed ‘depoliticisation’. Its results can be labelled and understood as a type of ‘neutralisation’ (Schmitt 1993). This deeply political practice, itself sometimes founded upon its own strategic myths, is a prime example of that which this work identifies as ‘ideology’. However, the notion of ideology at work here cannot be conflated with, or reduced to, the idea of myth.


One distinctive feature of ideology, at least within a Schmittian sense of this term, is the strategic misrepresentation of the contents of a particular agenda and set of specific interests associated with it, as though they were somehow universal, that is, as embodying ‘the national interest’, the ‘needs of humanity’, universally applicable ‘human rights imperatives’ etc. Through a policy and practice of disguised monopolisation, coercive homogenisation (one American-specific size fits all) and strategic deception, such forms of ideological misrepresentation seek to displace all other rival agendas and interests. In turn, this is clearly invidious to any surviving domestic or international types of substantive pluralism. Indeed, it risks becoming ‘imperialistic’ wherever a major power, or superpower, successfully implements and institutionalises such a supposedly universalistic orientation. Whilst ideologies and myths can overlap, the qualities just discussed are, perhaps, better classified as the hallmarks of a Schmittian understanding of ideology.


Those seeking to build up a more general Schmittian theory of the ideological dimension of legal discourse could start with his discussion of the ideology of humanity, discussed below, and then cross reference the results to his various accounts of the distinctly ideological aspects of liberalism. Others more interested in a critical analysis of how contemporary international law deploys notions of humanity and its various offshoots, such as ‘humanitarian intervention’, ‘crimes against humanity’ and ‘human rights’, are likely to find the later section devoted to this rich in arguments relevant to their project (Brown 2007).


Schmittian efforts to analyse legal ideologies as such are already critical in nature insofar as they typically present their cognitive claims as somehow self-evident and objective truths warranting uncritical acceptance. By contrast, Schmittian analysis seeks to expose the strictly relative and contingent qualities of legal ideologies, their artificially ‘constructed’ nature that is perpetually vulnerable to de-construction and – more generally – being reinterpreted otherwise. It thus analyses them against their own grain precisely to emphasise those distinctly ideological qualities and operations that are too often strategically glossed over as part of a self-legitimating strategy.


Here, ideological propositions are often disguised as straightforward and non-political statements of objective fact, as part of what is deemed ‘obvious’ to ‘common sense’, disconnected from any underpinning political agendas or material interests. In reversing such ideological operations of depoliticisation, Schmittian critics of law risk exposing the influence of their own ideological biases and particularistic interests: something that simply has to be accepted as a poetic and ironic form of justice. Schmitt recognises that the historically-informed Weberian sociology of concepts, which he occasionally practices as a research method, both addresses the presence of ideology within legal practices, and itself ‘presupposes a consistent and radical ideology’, where ‘radical’ means ‘comprehensively thought through’ (Schmitt 2005b: 42).


Yet, Schmitt expressly rejects the idea that ideology can be adequately understood through the lens of a Marxist dichotomy between materialism and idealism. The latter assigns the study of ideology to either an idealist approach, or reduces it to a mere ‘reflex’ or ‘reflections’ of a supposedly underlying material-economic process related to the capitalist ‘means of production’ (Schmitt 2005b: 42–3). The partial autonomy of cultural, intellectual and scientific realms, including those of a Marxist social science reliant upon a science/ideology dichotomy, is thereby subverted. Schmitt objects that Marxist theories of ideology begin by deploying an undialectical opposition between materialism and idealism, locating ideology as a derivative ‘superstructure’ to an all-determining economic sub-structure. As a result, all superstructural phenomena, ranging from religious belief to the scientific theory of relativity, are ‘explained’ in a reductive materialist fashion as mere causal products of underlying capitalist economic relations. This, of course, rebounds back to undermine the scientific status of the Marxist theory of ideology itself, rendering it little more than a ‘caricature’ of an academic approach (Schmitt 2005b: 42–3). By contrast, the Schmittian model of ideology is far closer to the cultural-interpretative orientation of Max Weber’s sociology of law, which – for all its emphasis on material and technological factors – Marxists typically reject as somehow ‘idealist’.


Liberal ideologies of legality


The category (perhaps more precisely categories) of ‘liberalism’ is complex; it needs to be redefined anew and variously within different moral, economic, jurisprudential and constitutional contexts. A Schmittian approach needs to retain some sense that the liberal constitutionalism of Mill and Dicey has some connection with – as well as a range of differences from – both the economic neo-liberalism of Adam Smith and Hayek, and liberal types of moral and political philosophy.


Provisionally, and as far as the present context is concerned, it is useful to identify as a key feature of liberalism the belief that a modern legal order consists of general ‘norms’ (rule and principles) that determine clearly the relationship of supposedly ‘free’ and ‘autonomous’ individual legal subjects to one another, in terms of their ‘positive’ rights and obligations contained, for instance, in various contractual agreements entered into without coercion.


For liberals, law is typically deemed to be an essentially positive institution, with the provision of a legal system one of only three absolutely necessary public services that even an ideal minimal or ‘night-watchman’ state is duty-bound to provide, alongside the police and military. Law is deemed a vital and positive institution. This is because it supposedly gives individuals a range of civil and political rights whose enforcement facilitates their ‘natural’ practice of political and economic individualism. It does so by subjecting state power and sovereignty to a series of institutional restraints, checks and balances including the separation of powers, judicial review, a prioritisation of purely civil and political ‘negative’ rights, and the rule of law (Schmitt 1988: 39–41; Schmitt 2005a: 7, 10–11). Other aspects of Schmitt’s complex, and not always consistent, understanding of liberalism in its various guises and disguises, will emerge and receive fuller illustration in many later sections of this book.


For present purposes, ‘liberal cosmopolitanism’ appears as a tendency within Kantian and neo-Kantian schools of legal and political theory to advance arguments founded upon the presumed validity of abstractly universal categories, including ‘global justice’, as key to the analysis of international law and international relations. It is currently a highly diverse movement that resists a single definition as divergent strands of cosmopolitan approaches span international criminal law, political theory, international relations, social theory and philosophy. However, Chandler concisely sums up a key tendency: ‘The aspiration to engage in, construct, or recognize the existence of a post-territorial political community, a community of broader humanity, has been articulated in liberal terms as cosmopolitanism, driven by global civil society’ (Chandler 2008: 53).


This tendency aims to supersede the traditional centrality of the modern nation state to domestic and transnational legal analysis. It does so by both promoting universalistic approaches to ‘democracy’, ‘human’ rights and ‘rights’ more generally, and endorsing the growth of ‘universal jurisdiction’ within international law and transnational bodies, such as the International Criminal Court. Typically, all counter-arguments founded upon national sovereignty as the least worst vehicle for optimally democratic forms of citizenship and governance, are presumed anachronistic, unduly conservative, even in one sense ‘false’ (Chandler 2008: 53–4).


Liberal cosmopolitanism typically interprets abstract universal categories and spatially-ungrounded entities as if they are transcendent to, and superior than, existing state-centred legal institutions (Zolo 1997). Hence, the concrete rights of citizens provided for by historically specific and politically contestable constitutional arrangements and statutory measures of particular nation states, are relegated to a lower position on the assumed ‘totem pole’ of rights, and indeed earmarked for redundancy and substitution by cosmopolitan alternatives. This is because of their historical contingency, limited territorial scope and particularity.


Here, supposedly universal-international ‘human rights’ aspiring to universal jurisdiction are located at the top of a presumed totem pole, and thereby effectively outrank and overpower ‘mere citizenship rights’, which belong only to a specific people and are restricted to a given territorial context of application and enforcement. This myth endorses the idea that one’s domestic legal obligations to obey the properly enacted domestic law, even of a murderous dictatorship that tortures to death dissenters, provides no legal defence to a charge before a international tribunal that such legally required actions constituted a ‘crime against humanity’ – as defined by supposedly ‘higher’ cosmopolitan law. To counter possible misunderstanding, this study addresses the liberal myths of cosmopolitan legality and justice and ‘global civil society’ in this, and no other, sense of this richly ambiguous term.


After such preliminary clarification of terms, let us now turn to Schmitt’s critical analysis of the ‘ideological’ framework of liberal legality. Schmitt does not claim that liberalism is the only ideological practice relevant to the study of law. However, compared with Marxist, Fascist and anarchist ideologies of the state and law, he devotes far more attention to liberal ideological practices. This is presumably because of their status as a historically achieved and pervasive orthodoxy, particularly when advanced in conjunction with both legal positivism and contemporary, that is, secularised, versions of natural law theories clothed in the rhetoric of ‘human rights’. The contradictions stemming from this marriage of incompatible theoretical foundations, which are rightly analysed within jurisprudence as alternatives, hardly requires further comment. Instead, the important thing here is to notice how effective liberal ideology can be in glossing over these and other contradictions; it does so by promoting an interpretative schema portraying a liberal model of legality as if it were a largely rational, coherent, worthwhile and essential element of social life as such. Schmitt’s analysis of this ideological practice is ‘radical’ in the sense that it seeks to go to the root of its core and underlying assumptions, biases and theoretical presuppositions.


Schmitt argues that, as a complex system of distinctly ideological thought, political commitment and belief, liberalism rests upon a series of largely taken-for-granted dichotomies (Schmitt 2004a: 52). The suspicion of liberal thought towards executive action in general, and administrative and judicial discretion in particular, rests upon the perceived need to set up ideal standards, and then depict institutional realities both through their lens and as their embodiment. These idealisations are founded upon the following distinctions treated as mutually exclusive and ‘either/or’ dichotomies (Schmitt 2004a: 97):



•  The separation of the scientific-positivist study of ‘the law’, defined as justified state norms, as distinct from an analytical focus upon empirical institutional questions concerning ‘legal application’ or enforcement, in which decisions are made with respect to individual cases.


•  General, given and enduring statutes, are distinguished from context-specific and ad hoc administrative measures, including delegated legislation and statutory instruments (Schmitt 2004b: 17, 53, 82–6).


•  The reasonableness of abstract general rules (or ratio), must be differentiated from the ‘alleged’ irrationality of blind and emotionally-charged political will (or voluntas) (Schmitt 2004a: 49, 59; Schmitt 2005a: 42, 45).


•  Legal norms, as idealised phenomena as distinct from the empirical segment of social reality being subjected to legal regulation in practice (Schmitt 2004a: 52).


•  The idealism of reasoned principled decision-making, which is grounded purely upon the requirements of legal norms considered in isolation, is distinguished from unprincipled and instrumental forms of pragmatism and utilitarianism, which are focused mainly upon the practical implications of different possible decisions (Schmitt 2004a: 4, 11, 70–1).


•  Law strictly defined as technical rules, as opposed to manifestations of politics and expressions of political goals through expressly recognised ‘policy factors’ (Schmitt 2004a: 97).


•  Objectively based and impersonal modes of legal judgement, as distinct from to subjective-grounded decision-making (Schmitt 2004a: 59, 65).


•  Objective truths of law identified through value-free legal science, as opposed to ideological assertions reflecting the social authority of the interpreter within a hierarchy (Schmitt 2004a: 49, 64).


Many of these radical ideological distinctions are, according to Schmitt, rooted in earlier, metaphysical and theological modes of thinking. However, secular forms of liberalism relevant to legal studies rely particularly upon the law/politics, normative/empirical and objective/subjective dichotomies. These have been expressed most emphatically in the work of Hans Kelsen and other legal positivists (Schmitt 2004a: 59).8 On the basis of the assumed truth of these dichotomies, liberalism claims to be able to distance the alleged ‘purity’ and ‘value-neutrality’ of strictly legal analysis and application from supposedly ‘outside’ influences deriving from all manner of political, moral and other commitments. However, the latter still contain inescapable constitutional questions concerning legitimacy, governmental effectiveness, power and sovereignty, which – despite being excluded from the ideological agenda of liberalism – continue to make their presence felt (Schmitt 2004a: 65).


Indeed, Schmitt maintains that liberal ideology typically dismisses the interjection of every supposedly ‘non-legal’ or ‘extra-juristic’ consideration as ideological, economic, sociological, moralistic or political (Schmitt 2004a: 65). Legal analysis is thereby redefined as the comparatively abstract and legalistic interpretation of doctrine (‘law in books’). This must be carried out in isolation from those empirical ‘contextual factors’ that other ‘non-legal’ disciplines, such as the sociology of law and criminology, draw upon to explain specific processes and events within the legal and constitutional systems (‘law in action’) (Schmitt 2004a: 62–3, 70–1).


Such ideological practices seek not only to make clear-cut and radical distinctions between supposedly mutually exclusive phenomena but also bestow constitutional legitimacy only upon one side, or half, of the various pairings and oppositions set out above. For example, generally applicable statutes are defined as exhibiting the essence of valid law in general because they manifest the principle of ‘equal treatment’ central to the liberal reinterpretation of the rule of law, whilst, at the same time, firmly disqualifying the other side of this pairing: namely, ad hoc discretionary measures directed at specific contexts, institutions or groups (Schmitt, 2004b: 81).


In Legality and Legitimacy, Schmitt addresses the normativism of the ideology of liberal constitutionalism, which he terms the ‘legislative state’. He presents an ideal type of model of the essential and defining qualities of this ideological framework, whilst acknowledging that, in practice, it appears mixed to various degrees with the features of other modern models of constitutional governance, which he terms the ‘administrative state’,9 ‘jurisdictional state’10 and ‘governmental state’11 (Schmitt 2004b: 4–5). Indeed, part of his critique of the liberal ideological presumptions of Kelsen’s theory is that it confuses this ‘ideal type’ with the more complex and changing realities of modern legal systems, which tend to combine, in varying proportions, features of each of these models (Schmitt 2004b: 4; Schmitt 2008a: 59 ff).


Schmitt defines the qualities and ideological assumptions of the legislative state as a constitutional system founded upon an underlying consensus expressed in the ‘norms’ that make up its constitutional and legal systems. It is a ‘particular type of political system that is distinctive in that norms … are the highest and decisive expression of the community will’. In this mode of governance, parliament is deemed to have a central and superior status, to be the site of sovereignty, because it is treated as the formal source of such norms. Despite possessing formal sovereignty, the legislature ‘does not govern directly, nor does it execute laws itself. It merely establishes valid norms, in whose name officials bound by statute to enforce the law exercise state power’ (Schmitt 2004b: 4).


According to liberal ideology, the legislative state is characterised by the inappropriately named liberal principle of the ‘rule of law’ where ‘“laws govern” not men, authorities or non-elected governments. More precisely: laws do not rule; they are valid only as norms’ (Schmitt 2004b: 4). In other words, insofar as state officials follow the implications of legal norms that authorise and govern their functions, no one in particular ‘rules’ in the sense of being able to assert individualised and personal authority over others. Whilst there is clearly a relationship of ‘subordination to authority’, this concerns not the citizen’s relationship to public officials but rather the latter’s subordination to prior legal norms, which alone authorise their actions in relation to individual citizens. An extreme liberal normativism reduces the conception of the state to that allegedly closed and unified system of norms comprising formal constitutional provisions. Hence, the constitution is treated as the state, with the ‘state treated as something imperative that corresponds to norms, and one sees in the state only a system of norms, a “legal” order, which does not actually exist, though it is valid in normative terms. The legal order, nonetheless, establishes an absolute concept of the constitution because a closed, systematic unity of norms is implemented and rendered equivalent to the state’ (Schmitt 2008a: 63). Lacking any share of state sovereignty, which is ascribed exclusively to law itself, the official’s authority over a citizen stops at the point where they attempt to act beyond the authorisation stemming from the meaning of relevant norms, that is, to exercise extra-normative power: ‘There is no ruling and no [law free] power at all anymore. Whoever exercises power and government acts “on the basis of law” or “in the name of the law”. He does nothing other than what a valid legal norm permits jurisdictionally’ (Schmitt 2004b: 4). Here, regulation by generally applicable norms prevails to the point where ‘all other public functions and substantive affairs must be subordinated to them’ (Schmitt 2004b: 3). This normative reductionism has negative implications for the analysis of welfare state discretion, which will be discussed later.


For liberal ideology’s conception of the ‘rule of law’ to operate as objectively as possible, for it to embody state sovereignty, the norms themselves must be optimally determinate and positive: ‘impersonal, that is, general and pre-established, norms that are meant to be lasting and that have a definable, determinable content’ (Schmitt 2004b: 3–4). In addition, the liberal constitutional doctrine of the separation of powers is institutionalised so that: ‘law and legal application, law-maker and officials responsible for legal application, are separated from one another’ (Schmitt 2004b: 4). Equally, the legislative and the executive functions are kept separate, so that sovereignty is in effect dispersed, and then subjected to a system of balances between executive, parliament and judiciary designed to counteract the concentration of substantive state power (Schmitt 2004b: 53). Schmitt insists that this doctrine of the separation of powers is a ‘directly necessary, constructive, fundamental principle of the legislative state, in which not men and persons rule, but rather where norms are valid’ (Schmitt 2004b: 4).


Because sovereignty attaches to a system of norms, not to specific officials or individuals by virtue of their extra-normative status as serfs, freeman and lords, earlier feudal conceptions of hierarchical social power at whose apex stands a divinely appointed monarch, no longer apply. In this sense, within a modern legislative state ‘where only impersonal, valid norms are applied’, there is no longer any ‘rule’, ‘governance’, ‘obedience’ and ‘subordination’ at all. The sole criteria for the legitimacy of state actions and the ‘state exercise of power’ are that of their ‘legality’. In other words, the system of legislative norms comprising the legal and constitutional systems is therefore ‘closed’, in the sense that either a government act is recognised as legitimate because it is validly authorised by prior norms, or it is not (Schmitt 2008a: 62). There can be neither extra-normative sources of constitutional legitimacy, nor extra-normative grounds for challenging the legitimacy of coercive state actions:



A closed system of legality grounds the claim to obedience and justifies the suspension of every right of resistance. In this regard, the specific manifestation of the law is the statute, while legality is the particular justification of state coercion.


(Schmitt 2004b: 4)


For Schmitt, liberal ideological practices elevate their own preferred model of legality through a process of denigrating and displacing as constitutionally illegitimate alternative social democratic and welfare state orientations. As such, liberalism acts as a classic monopoly hostile to effective competition. For instance, in practice, the system of ideological prioritisation of one side of a dichotomy discussed above works to disadvantage the status afforded to judicial and other forms of sovereign discretion because it is most closely associated with those elements of these dichotomies that are disqualified and excluded. In this context, the identification of aspects of, say, discretion and a personal element of choice between alternative judicial interpretations of both ‘material’ facts and ‘relevant’ legal measures, becomes immediately reinterpreted as falling on the prohibited side of a subjective/objective dichotomy (Schmitt 2004a: 65, 91). In turn, this form of ideological reinterpretation provokes the conclusion that, for liberalism, the forms of administrative and judicial discretion essential to classic welfare state measures necessarily represents an example of constitutionally illicit forms of ‘arbitrariness’, a politicised misuse of state power threatening the ‘basic rights’ of individual freedom, freedom of contract and private property rights (Schmitt 1996a: 21, 41; Schmitt 2004b: 20; Schmitt 2008a: 63). From liberalism’s ideological perspective, the manifestation of administrative discretion associated with modern welfare state interventions into civil society is potentially ‘a dictatorship unbounded by norms and without spirit’ (Schmitt 2004a: 11). It represents an essentially ‘arbitrary’ exercise of unwarranted and unnecessary authority that not only pollutes but also destabilises the legal system’s core of settled doctrinal meanings.


Schmitt gives the example of affronts to liberal standards stemming from allegedly ‘arbitrary’ forms of judicial sentencing that fail to ‘faithfully enforce statutes’, or where judges personally invent new criminal offences not based upon prior statutes, established rules and strictly legal principles (Schmitt 2004a: 28). According to this ideological projection, discretionary decision-making within the legal sphere allegedly represents the unwarranted and unnecessary intrusion of ‘subjective’ factors into a process that both can, and should, be strictly ‘objective’. Schmitt claims that such decision-making is redefined as a fall from grace (Schmitt 2004a: 65).


Liberal ideologies make the assumption that the discretionary ‘interventions’ of state officials into the workings of civil society will always be questionable unless they can be clearly shown to meet at least two decisive tests: first, that these officials are clearly acting with definite and express authority under a specific power; and secondly, that such officials are exercising their decision-making strictly in accordance with the precise requirements of a given set of legal norms or ‘meta-rules’ (‘rules’ of statutory interpretation, the doctrine of precedent, statutory guidelines etc) (Schmitt 2004a: 85–6). Where these two vital tests are met, the belief is that the validity of a decision will become explicable not in terms of the subjectivity and personal authority of those who actually decided the case, their ideological background, gender, generation, class, race, economic interests and so forth, but rather in terms of the objective meanings of the relevant norms themselves (Schmitt 2004a: 18).


On the dubious assumption that the dichotomies it projects are well-founded and strictly necessary to legal thought, liberal ideology promotes the idea that one can study both law and parliamentary law-making as independent topics in their own right; and to the exclusion of the highly pragmatic and selective application and enforcement of law by a variety of different institutions and agencies.


Schmitt argues that the common law emphasis on case-by-case decision-making as an independent source of law is more flexible than continental types of legal formalism. However, the attempt to detect an underlying ratio decidendi, the elusive ‘reason for the decision’ defined as a given norm – and hence ‘binding precedent’, still recuperates aspects of liberal-positivism’s one-sided emphasis upon rules and meta-rules as expressing the essence of law.


For liberals, the topic of officials exercising their discretion during both the interpretation and application of legal measures to specific circumstances falls on the ‘wrong side’ of two distinctions: generally applicable statutes versus situation-specific administrative measures and, secondly, ratio versus voluntas (Schmitt 2004a: 18).12 Liberal ideology typically rejects this possibility in favour of a largely abstract and legal positivist analysis of law. This is defined as a closed and coherent system of abstract and isolated norms, and judicial interpretations of both the meaning and scope of such norms presumed to be largely devoid of any policy rationale.


Furthermore, according to Schmitt, these underlying either/or dichotomies also make possible a series of ‘presumed congruence and harmonies’. Whilst vindicating a distinctly liberal model of the rule of law, these generate additional negative interpretations of the nature of judicial and official discretion. Such interpretations include the assimilation of the following: first, the reduction of the concept of justice into strict compliance with legality, leading to a model of merely formal and corrective justice, not substantive political or distributive justice (Schmitt 2004b: 29). Secondly, there is the assimilation of ‘law in general’ into generally applicable statutes and substance-free ‘due process’ requirements.


By contrast, any potential legitimacy possessed by the discretionary exercise of sovereign power depends, at least partly, upon an affirmation of precisely those terms of these either/or pairings, which liberalism collapses, disqualifies and expels from consideration. For example, the perceived legitimacy of discretionary judgement relies upon its pragmatic and flexible role in actually achieving substantive public policy goals and values, such as politically defined conceptions of ‘social justice’ or ‘social inclusion’. These can, perhaps, only be optimised through context-specific and responsive forms of administrative regulation attuned to the perceived needs of affected parties (Schmitt 2004b: 19, 28–9).


Closely related to the liberal ideology of the ‘rule of law’ is the assertion that the exercise of state authority, including that of the judges, should take place subject to generally applicable and enduring statutes related, for example, to the modern welfare state, such as planning regulation, public health and social security. This ideology distinguishes ad hoc administrative ‘measures’ from the generality and objectivity of statutes and (in the common law context, long-established constitutional conventions with the force of law),13 which are supposed to apply to all citizens equally. The former are directed to specific contingencies and groups, such as ad hoc redistributive windfall taxes (Schmitt 2004b: 17). General statutes are supposed to realise liberalism’s ideal of a closed and gapless system of constitutional legality of all state actions under the rule of law, which is respectful of the individual’s basic civil and political rights (Schmitt 2004a: 9).


Schmitt’s analysis of liberal ideology further suggests that, insofar as officials strictly respect the requirements of the rule of law, then their actions and decisions are expected to exemplify principles of strict ‘legality’. This is typically defined as an exclusively rule-based type of decision-making involving the application of clear and precise norms in a manner that is itself governed by the meta-rules of precedent, statutory interpretation, sentencing guidelines and so forth. He claims that the liberal’s ideological approach to official discretion assumes that legal rules and neutral procedures for their application, ie. ‘meta-rules’, are generally ‘determinate’, in the sense of being clearly defined and generally unambiguous. It follows that they must possess sufficiently clear, unambiguous and determinate content to be capable of retaining a core of fixed meaning(s) across every actual and potential application to a range of different factual contexts. In other words, optimal legality is achievable by means of the enforcement of liberal conceptions of legality, premised upon the deployment of generalised, objective legal norms with a fixed and determinate core of stable meaning, further supported by neutral procedures and meta-rules to guide how rules should be applied to facts. The legality of decision-making depends upon subsuming the unique facts and claims of the particular case under general rules, applied in a neutral manner. It follows that they must possess sufficient determinate content to be capable of retaining a core of fixed meaning across every actual and potential application to a range of different factual contexts. In other words, optimal restraint of judicial creativity is achievable by means of the enforcement of liberal conceptions of legality premised upon the deployment of generalised, objective legal norms with a fixed and determinate core of stable meaning, further supported by neutral procedures and meta-rules to guide how rules should be applied to facts. Such determinacy thus ensures the possibility of standards of legality.


From this ideological standpoint, the rules and principles of legal doctrine are, and should be, regarded as essentially determinate to the point where it is possible to define precisely what they mean within any particular context of application. The ‘determinate’ nature of legal norms and neutral rule-based procedures and guidelines for judicial decision-making, that is, doctrines of precedent, rules of statutory interpretation, etc., both can and should restrain official discretion. For Schmitt, the irony is that these are attempts to cut down discretion within the application of law through meta-rules whose application in practice multiplies this phenomenon (Schmitt 2004a: 85). In short, standards of legality require that judges apply statutory rules in an apparently ‘objective’ manner consistent with various meta-rules designed to further minimise the scope for judicial discretion.


According to Schmitt’s analysis, liberal ideologies aims to promote a strictly rule and meta-rule-based type of decision-making because this is supposed to represent a defining characteristic of a properly functioning modern constitutional state enshrining the rule of law. This feature allegedly sets it apart from, and superior to, the comparative ‘lawlessness’ of both earlier feudal regimes and more recent socialist governments (Schmitt 2004b: 18). Schmitt suggests that liberals follow Hobbes in believing that the only alternative to a legalistic model of decision-making strictly governed by given and determinate rules, neutral procedures and meta-rules, is a return to a proverbial state of nature. That is, a condition of unimaginable strife, desperate disorder and insecurity of both life and property, an ‘orderless struggle of all against all’ (Schmitt 2004a: 62). For example, liberalism requires modern courts to renounce outcome-driven, moralistic or ad hoc forms of decision-making, sometimes equated with equity, in which judges decide in favour of whichever party they find most deserving in terms of criteria of justice and good conscience. According to Schmitt, liberalism thereby generates a distinctly positivistic view of law and the preconditions of a stable, and hence predictable, type of legal order based upon a closed and autonomous system of coherent rules and principles – or ‘legal norms’ (Schmitt 2004a: 65). This positive ideal claims that, properly understood, law consists of a closed system of rules, underpinned by even more general principles.


According to this ideological model, legal norms occupy a completely different and more elevated plane than mere factual events and actions, a position that allows us to identify liberal ideologies as committed to one type of ‘normativism’ involving either a reduction of non-normative elements of law to norms, or their displacement altogether. The objectivity of law as a stable system of norms stands over and above both the flux of the political process of its creation and reform, and its status ensured by objective application and enforcement of independent judicial experts. Legal norms must be analysed jurisprudentially by addressing questions of technical validity, not in terms of politics or their policy-effectiveness. Their supposedly elevated state explains why no factual event, no matter how violent or physically destructive, can destroy the continuing validity of a general norm. For Schmitt, the crucial point here is this model’s underlying conception of law as essentially a rule-governed, and hence orderly, system of rules from which all sources of uncertainty, including empirical contingencies, have been rigorously expelled. Law is thus ideologically reinterpreted as a system of:



[P]redetermined, general rules and statutes, which are independent of the concrete state of affairs, every manifestation of legal life – every command, every measure, every contract, every decision – turns into a norm. Every concrete order and community disintegrates into a series of effective norms, whose ‘unity’ or ‘system’ is, in turn, only normative. Order essentially consists of the fact that a concrete situation corresponds to general norms by which it is measured.


(Schmitt 2004a: 52)


In short, according to liberalism’s approach, the only legally significant aspect of disputes consists of how such situations can be reinterpreted in terms of – and through the lens of – doctrinal rules, and those requirements and tests for specific remedies contained in these norms. As already noted, the latter is defined as a closed and generally coherent system of rules and principles. This system is supposed to be utterly detached from the clash of interests, or compromise agreements, or even the distinctive internal way of life of the sub-cultural order of a concrete institutional order within which it is taking place (Schmitt 2004a: 94). Whilst the norms themselves are presumed to be ‘in order’, a generally seamless web lacking contradictions or gaps, the existence of a clash of material interests between the parties to a dispute, and hence factual ‘disorder’ in the real-life field of application, is deemed to be entirely irrelevant. Their only relevance is as a source of ‘evidence’ for a doctrinal argument relating to the applicability of a particular legal norm and remedy (do the facts fall inside or outside the doctrinal requirements of a rational legal order), the result of which is to pronounce a certain action as either lawful or unlawful:



All valid norms for as long as they are valid, are naturally always ‘in order’; the disorder of the concrete situation, in contrast, does not interest the normativist who is only interested in the norm. Viewed in this [legalistic] way, the concrete state-of-affairs can never in a normativist sense, be disorder as opposed to order.


(Schmitt 2004a: 52)


Such doctrinal-normative ‘order’ persists because the answer to any legal issue raised by empirical disputes both can, and should, be arrived at exclusively by reference to the neutral tests and objective requirement of the norms themselves, which remain aloof from, and unaffected by, the concrete reality of the situation (Schmitt 2004a: 65).


Liberal ideology thereby relies upon its own projected dichotomy between norms and facts to justify its assertion that the concrete application of legal provisions to empirical matters both can, and should, operate as an almost mechanical process akin to a train company adhering to the stipulations of its own published timetable, or even the purchase of bottled drinks from a vending machine (Schmitt 2004a: 53). In each case, the users of the system who conform to pre-given and determinate normativist requirements can, according to liberal ideology, reasonably expect to receive a measure of certainty of outcome. This is because each element of the legal system follows set rules, routine adherence to which regularly trigger standardised results in an orderly, and hence predictable, fashion. It is their comparative autonomy vis-à-vis every instance of their application that allows us to identify these rules with a high degree of certainty (Schmitt 2004a: 65).


According to liberal ideology, doctrinal certainty is possible because judges can arrive at a single correct answer to legal questions if, but only if, they strictly apply the objective tests and requirements contained in the clearly identifiable contents of the relevant norms. This is because the ‘answer’ to any distinctly legal question arising during litigation is assumed to be already substantially contained in the objective meaning of the inviolable norms themselves (Schmitt 2004a: 65). However, certainty in relation to the meaning and applicability of legal doctrine is possible only if those who interpret and apply the law succeed in subordinating their subjectivity to the ‘objective’ meaning of the contents of these rules themselves, thereby respecting the principle of legality already discussed.


In short, on Schmitt’s account, liberal ideology needs to give the ideals of certainty and predictability an extremely high priority as goals for a healthy system of law and well-ordered and stable civil society, in which citizens can trust in the reliability of both legal advice and their various arrangements. The problem that such ideology glosses over and suppresses is that many of the factual events that impact upon legal developments are essentially ‘exceptional’, that is, unpredictable and unexpected. In turn, these can result in judges generating decisions with similar qualities. Positivism betrays its own principle of positivity by discounting this element of the concretely experienced reality of law (Schmitt 2005a: 6–7, 13–15).


Although liberal ideology within the legal sphere typically takes the form of a normativism which renounces reference to extra-doctrinal policy or other contextual factors, it conveniently exempts itself from this prohibition. Indeed, liberals typically claim, or at least tacitly assume, that doctrinal standards of certainty secure both stability and ‘calculability’ within the ‘external’ realm of commerce and society more generally (Schmitt 2004a: 65). This, in turn, allegedly minimises the cost of litigation because lawyers can – by reference to the objective content of legal norms – generally predict which way a judge would decide a dispute if the matter ultimately went to trial. The party with the weaker case, a matter that expert legal advisers can definitively identify, is given every incentive to settle legal disputes through negotiation. Hence, liberals can claim that it is vital that the quality of certainty characterises both legal doctrine and its meta-rule-governed judicial application. Certainty is also deemed to exhibit the alleged virtue of not only preserving the integrity and reputation of the legal system, but also enabling calculability and planning within civil society more generally.


The model of ‘normal’ social life presupposed by liberal ideology is that of legalism writ large, that is, a ‘calculable functioning of human relationships … as a mere function of predetermined, calculable, general rules’ (Schmitt 2004a: 53). It is claimed that one result of a general adherence to clear legal rules is that civil society can operate smoothly in a standardised and predictable fashion. The ‘trust’ that members of civil society rightly place in the reliability, security and robust quality of transactions regulated by legal norms would, it is claimed, be betrayed if ad hoc, consequentialist and case-by-case forms of legal decision-making were ever allowed to introduce uncertainty (Schmitt 2004a: 66):



Insofar as this positivism furnishes a philosophical legal foundation, it leads in the intellectual direction of the interests of an individualistic legal-certainty and appeals to the fact that it would be wrong to disappoint … the expectation, and the ‘trust’ of the legal community evoked through the statute. Therein one beholds the ‘righteousness of positivity’.


(Schmitt 2004a: 53)


For Schmitt, ‘individualistic legal-certainty’ with respect to both the meaning of legal rules and reliable predictions concerning how these rules will be judicially applied to a range of actual or future factual situations, represents a key ideological value that also gives effect to a vital constitutional imperative (Schmitt 2004a: 66, 90). It provides the basis for other characteristics of liberalism, including ‘well-founded’ attempts to strictly limit the legislature’s deployment of ‘general clauses’ in statutes, such as references to ‘good faith’, ‘reasonable in all the circumstances’ or ‘in the interests of justice’. Such broad terms, often associated with welfare state provisions, are deemed to be problematic. This is because their single correct meaning of the rules within a closed, unified and complete system of strictly internal norms cannot be ‘pinned down’ in advance with any degree of certainty (Schmitt 2004a: 90–1):



Schmitt further claims that such general clauses represent the ‘cuckoo’s egg’ in the nest of ‘the liberal legal system’ (Schmitt 2004a: 91).


Liberalism’s ideological projection of its notion of strict legality is, of course, entirely self-serving because it generates an image of liberal legality as pre-empting an ultimate collapse into anarchy. Liberal ideology thereby raises itself up to the vital and elevated constitutional position of ‘resolute defender’ of threatened legality, order and security. Furthermore, the importance liberal ideology places on the interrelated values of legal certainty, the alleged ‘determinacy’ of doctrine, and the resulting ‘predictability’ of law, sets up an ideal of legalistic decision-making, seldom borne out in practice, thereby precluding empirical issues and analysis (Schmitt 2004a: 65).


More generally, the rule of law principle becomes ideologically reinterpreted to mean the complete domination of the legal system by liberalism’s own preferred definition of law: law as a closed and politically independent system of generally applicable and objective rules. Hence, Schmitt claims that in order to comply with liberal standards of the rule of law, any decision concerning the legal rights and obligations of specific parties in a concrete case must be clearly ‘mediated by pre-established, general norms’ and fully and exclusively manifest the rule of these norms themselves (Schmitt 2004b: 5). Decision-making by reference to extra-normative standards thus violates the expectations generated by liberalism’s ideological model of the rule of law.


A statute, constitutional convention, or long-standing common law principle of individual liberty, has an especially elevated place within liberal ideology, as an authoritative legal norm to which all else must be subjected. As an expression of the supremacy of parliamentary sovereignty, liberalism gives general statutes such a priority that, in the event of any conflict, they can even negate the results of a democratic referendum relating, for example, to the meaning and scope of human rights within the United Kingdom (Schmitt 2004b: 73). By contrast, the administrative measures of a welfare state are, it is claimed on the ideological basis of preferences for a minimal or ‘night-watchman’ state, believed to open the door to officials exercising a distinctly discretionary form of governance inconsistent with the requirements of the rule of law. The latter, to which the pejorative term ‘arbitrary’ is frequently attached – as if extra-legal guidelines and conventions are irrelevant in principle – is supposed to be based largely upon their own political values and public sector ideologies. Although dressed up as delegated or secondary legislation, in practice any administrative measures that empower such officials is supposed to represent an essentially extra-constitutional – and therefore problematic – form of governance (Schmitt 2004b: 4).


Difficulties and contradictions with liberal ideologies


Schmitt argues that, at empirical, policy and conceptual levels, liberal ideologies lead to many negative consequences. The remainder of this section will address these unfortunate results for any realistic form of legal analysis concerning the conception of law, the alleged ‘determinacy’ of legal norms/categories, the inevitably interpretative nature of the legal process and, finally, the creative or legislative aspect of the judicial role. To ensure and reiterate the credibility of its overall ideological orientation, however, these difficulties and contradictions have to be ignored, glossed over or otherwise disguised.


An unduly narrow definition of law


The first cluster of difficulties Schmitt identifies concern liberalism’s ideological deployment and enforcement of an unduly narrow definition of law, and hence legal analysis, research and education. Its positivist or ‘black letter’ model of law effectively reduces the field of law to the study of a closed, given and unified system of doctrinal rules detached from social contexts of emergence and application (Schmitt 2008a: 62 ff). This is because other social and political elements, which prior to the emergence of liberalism were generally considered essential, such as sovereign decision and the re-establishing of either a social order, or sub-cultural institutional orders challenged by a dispute, have been effectively eliminated from legal analysis and discussion.


And yet without a symbiotic interrelationship between, for example, a family court and the practice of family life, and between law and society more generally, the legal field is arguably reduced to an arid sterility, whilst social practices are condemned to subjugation by a legal regime indifferent to the ebb and flow of real-life values and changing social conditions and orientations. In other words, for Schmitt, liberal-positivist ideologies are detrimental insofar as they fail to take account of how any field of legal doctrine necessarily draws upon the pre-existing and independently constituted ‘concrete order’ of an area of social practice, such as family life or democratic political culture, as this is being concretely lived and experienced by participants (Schmitt 2004a: 50–1). Liberal ideology endorses a form of Kelsenian legal positivism that is structurally incapable of incorporating the lessons available from a sociologically and historically informed and substantive model of sovereignty understood as an expression of ‘political will’. However, articulations of political will are precisely what underpins the possibility and continues to pervade and determine the operations of a modern legal system, including ongoing law reform agenda, and this pervasive dimension is only most obviously present within exceptional contexts, such as a wartime state of emergency (Schmitt 2005a: 6, 13).


For example, Schmitt expressly contrasts his own realist interpretation of constitutions as historically specific embodiments of the collective political values and will of a specific people and concrete type of state formation, which helps cement a substantive ‘condition of political unity’ and a concretely existing and distinctive type of order and orientation of a specific state, with the emptiness and formalism of a purely normativist interpretation. That is, a constitution reinterpreted as a ‘closed system of norms’ that allegedly comprises the sole and absolute legal significance of the state itself (Schmitt 2008a: 59). Schmitt thereby aims to highlight the abstract character of any form of legal analysis dominated by the ideological agenda of liberal normativism, its lack of sociological realism concerning, for example, how specific relations of power, command and rule involving concrete forms of supremacy and subordination permeate both public law and concrete forms of the state’s existence, or state forms, such as aristocracy, republicanism and democracy (Schmitt 2008a: 60). It is patently absurd to seek to analyse constitutions, such as those of America, Germany, Ireland and France and post-communist Eastern European states, in purely normativist terms, that is, divorced from any consideration of the successful political revolutions that first made their distinctive value-orientations possible in the first place. The normativism promoted by liberal ideologies cannot but generate a purely formal conception of sovereignty lacking empirical realism, as if laws create, modify and apply themselves independently of interest-driven social actors and institutional processes. As Schmitt notes, ‘It is also possible to designate the constitution as “sovereign” in this [Kelsenian-normativist] sense, although that is in itself an unclear form of expression. For only something existing in concrete terms can properly be sovereign. A merely valid norm cannot be sovereign’ (Schmitt 2008a: 63).


The liberal idea that it is legal norms, conceived of in liberal-positivist terms, that ‘rules’ over society, found expression in ‘bourgeois liberal’ radicalism in the early and mid-19th-century Europe. This belief tends to designate the provisions of formal written documents as if they constituted a ‘sovereign’ power. This ideological ‘personalification’ has, as its flip side, the equally remarkable ‘depersonalisation’ of really existing and empirically ascertainable forms of personalised rule, command and asymmetrical power, including articulations of citizens’ democratic self-governance. This classic instance of ideological depoliticisation evades the reciprocal mediation of public law and substantive politics (Schmitt 2008a: 63).


Another difficulty with liberalism’s ideological conception of law concerns its lack of historical analysis and resulting preference for static modes of legal analysis concerned, for example, with ‘the meaning’ of ownership or property or contractual agreement. In this context, Schmitt complains that ‘the sharp separation of static and dynamic has something artificial and violent about it’ (Schmitt 2008a: 61). Indeed, he contrasts such normativism, whose modes of analysis are typically static, abstracted and non-contextual, with more historically oriented and process-oriented approaches to constitutional law. These recognise the ongoing ‘dynamic’ and forever emerging element of social and political will-formation and collective ‘decision’, including revolutions, as an important source and dynamic of law. That is:



[T]he principle of the dynamic emergence of political unity, of the process of constantly renewed formation and emergence of this unity from a fundamental or ultimately effective power and energy. The state is understood not as something existing, resting statically, but as something emerging. As something always arising anew. Political unity must form itself daily out of various opposing interests, opinions, and aspirations. … it must integrate itself.


(Schmitt 2008a: 61)


Because by means of its law/politics dichotomy liberalism brackets out analysis of ‘the political’ in favour of its own depoliticised and narrow conception of ‘the legal’, it prevents itself from recognising the politics of law, its rootedness in the social formation and ongoing reiteration of collective political will-formation, including the various forms of citizens’ participation within the political process (Schmitt 2008a: 61). And yet the reality remains that successful political and sometimes even social revolutions often lie at the heart of new constitutions and constitutional settlements, such that constitutional history remains one aspect of a wider social history of political transformation. Here, the normative content of such constitutions, its various clauses and articles studied by public lawyers, cannot be understood other than as an articulation of these new and ongoing political realities. Normativism remains fixated upon that which is ‘positive’ or positively ‘given’, and thus fails to recognise the extent to which modern law:



Schmitt argues that liberal ideology’s narrowly positivist and formalistic conception of law, reliant upon questionable dichotomies and one-sided conceptual prioritisations, leads to other difficulties. In particular, liberal-positivism remains overly concerned with internal legal system issues concerning technical origins and respect for meta-rules; it thereby fails to account for the effectiveness of legal norms in practice, the extent to which they are obeyed and achieve their stated or implied goals (Caldwell 1997: 86). Thus, another strand of Schmitt’s critique of liberal ideology is indebted less to jurisprudence than to empirically informed social science studies of law, which today are termed socio-legal studies. His criticism insists that viable forms of legal analysis cannot avoid drawing upon the resources of social science methods and the results of concrete empirical and contextual studies of law in action, which for example treat the constitution as a really existing cluster of institutional practices prevailing at a given time (Schmitt 2008a: 59–60, 62–3).


According to Schmitt, properly conceived legal analysis is an interdisciplinary project that draws necessarily on the detailed results of historical, philosophical and social science studies. This, of course, contrasts most markedly with the normativism of liberal ideology, manifested most emphatically within the ‘pure theory’ promoted by Kelsen conceived of as part of a ‘stand-alone’ form of ‘legal science’. Schmitt thus insists on the appropriateness of a distinctly contextual form of legal analysis, which gives close attention to the ‘problem of the realisation of law’ (Schmitt 2005a: 21). This broader model of law and legal analysis contrasts markedly with how the narrowly doctrinal approach of liberal normativism focuses on norms ‘as such’, to the strict exclusion of questions concerning the nature and differential political impact of both judicial interpretation and application of legal norms and other considerations of the politics of selective law enforcement/non-enforcement.


Liberal ideological conceptions of law move uneasily between two equally extreme and mutually incompatible theoretical positions. On the one hand, they promote their own key and individualistic values, interests and concerns, such as private property, freedom of contract and negative rights against the state as an inalienable ‘natural right’ (or, to use more recent secularised terminology, ‘human right’): one that expresses a law of human reason and principles of reasonableness itself. Legal norms that articulate these against the state, even the latter’s democratically enacted legislative initiatives, are afforded an ultimate, even absolute status as constitutionally protected ‘basic rights’. In other words, such individualistic values, interests and institutions are endorsed as alleged expressions of ‘natural rights’ and reason itself. Hence, legal norms articulating and facilitating these are elevated to a status that is ‘prior to and above every political being’ (Schmitt 2008a: 64). On the other hand, this classic natural law position is contradicted by the fact that modern liberal ideologies of law also ground themselves in the normativism of a type of legal positivism. The latter’s starting point is, of course, the celebrated separation between questions of ‘what is’ the law and issues concerning what it ‘ought to be’ in a moral or political sense, which reaches an extreme point in Kelsen’s pure theory of law.


Schmitt recognises that a case can, perhaps, be made for grounding legal analysis in either of these two theoretical positions. However, liberalism’s ideological practice of merging this marriage of incompatibles, and shifting in an unprincipled and opportunistic way between them, cannot but generate all manner of contradictions. Whilst properly enacted legislation providing for the complete nationalisation of private property would be rejected by one strand of liberal ideology as an attack on universal and absolute human rights whose validity is independent of their recognition by the ‘positive-legal reality’ of domestic state law, the other positivist element would surely have to recognise it as valid law. That is, as an actual and positive provision whose normative content needs to be accepted and analysed purely as such, free from any ‘external’ moral or political objections. This is because for such liberal types of legal positivism only positively enacted laws, whose pedigree is fully compliant with given constitutional protocols, count as valid law at all.


The positivist dimension of liberal positivism reduces to the tautology of an uncritical affirmation of what is the case because it currently exists: ‘something is valid when it is valid and because it is valid’ (Schmitt 2008a: 64). Questions of whether property ‘should’, in principle, be privately or publicly owned fall outside the scope of objective legal analysis and jurisprudence respectful of its own limits. In other words, liberalism’s distinctly political project of normativism may perhaps exhibit a certain coherence if considered strictly in its own terms, that is, as a polemical rationalisation of one set of socio-economic interests against all rival agendas. However, when it is articulated in the manner of Kelsenian legal positivism, for example, as a ground for a supposed non-political or ‘pure’ theory of law, blatant contradictions and ‘confusions’ inevitably arise whose ramifications in practice can be disguised but not eliminated.


In turn, this difficulty emphasises the need for such ‘pure theories’ to be reinterpreted as primarily ideological in nature, as disguised jurisprudential rationalisations for the domination of society by a specific cluster of interests, concerns and values. The status quo has to be accepted as valid because it exists as the status quo, unless and until it exhibits elements that are incompatible with core liberal values. Where this arises, ‘higher’ natural/human rights suddenly become relevant standards for constitutional legitimacy of even duly enacted democratic legislation. For all its self-promoting appeals to reason and science, Schmitt suggests that liberal ideologies culminate in a shabby form of political opportunism incompatible with any principled position. If a legal and constitutional system embodying liberal values is to be justified it has to be on grounds that the substance of its core principles are coherent, self-consistent and rationally compelling, and ‘valid in themselves by virtue of their reason and justice without regard for their “positive” validity’ (Schmitt 2008a: 64–5). Schmitt flatly denies that, as an empirical matter, a closed constitutional system of ‘pure norms’ actually exists. He thereby charges liberal ideologists, such as Kelsen, with promoting an essentially arbitrary and unrealistic account of law as if it somehow exhibited a ‘systematic unity and order’ (Schmitt 2008a: 65).


Exaggerating the determinacy of legal doctrine


Another series of difficulties created by the application of liberal ideology concerns its exaggeration of the ‘determinacy’ of pre-defined legal norms. To vindicate its own assumptions and overall belief system, liberal ideology thus promotes the idea that, within a modern liberal regime characterised by the rule of law and an independent judiciary, legal rules and principles are generally ‘determinate’ that is, definable, stable and – at their core – largely fixed.


To counter the threat of indeterminacy, and hence doctrinal ‘uncertainty’, liberal ideology insists each and every example of law application, no matter the degree of factual variation and uniqueness in the circumstances, both can and should – as a matter of reason and logic – be subsumed as an instance of a general ‘type’ of case for which standardised rules apply: ‘Every law is reduced to the norm, which is separated from the circumstances; the rest is “mere fact” and the opportunity for factual “confirmation of the law”’ (Schmitt 2004a: 62). In other words, to remain rational and scientific, legal analysis should only address the facts of any individual law report insofar as the reason for the decision (ratio decidendi) gives effect to a more general doctrinal rule. Students of law are thus supposed to ‘learn the case-law’ only to illustrate formalistic models of legal doctrine, not to examine the empirical vagaries of judicial practice in this area.


For Schmitt, this formalistic reinterpretation of the legal process leads to an essentially unrealistic account of law in practice, of how law is actually lived and experienced by those involved in, and affected by, its institutional practices. Kelsen, a militant proponent of liberal positivism, takes such normativism to its extreme when he claims that legal science is not concerned with relations of substantive power, real effective governance and extra-judicial authority. This is because these phenomena belong to the extra-normative and excluded causal-empirical realm of ‘what is’ (Kelsen 1911: 226–7, 396–7). Kelsen, by contrast, rejected the ‘command’ or ‘will-based’ positivism of Bentham that has been more influential for Anglo-American legal positivists, such as Hart, as violating the key law/politics, is/ought, empirical/normative science oppositions. For this ideology, it is law that ‘rules’, and, from a strictly juristic perspective, ‘the state is a purely normative phenomenon. The state is: ‘an ideal system, a system of coercive norms, in whose validity its specific existence rests’ (Kelsen, Staatsbegriff, quoted and translated in Caldwell 1997: 94).


This ideological conception of the ‘determinacy’ of legal doctrines positively reinforces liberalism’s wider model of the rule of law. This is because state officials, including judges, are – it is claimed – positively required to adhere to pre-defined, precise and clear standards, something which allows little scope for legitimate forms of discretion. For those who accept this ideological vision, it follows that a legal decision is ‘correct’ insofar as any other ‘reasonable’ decision-maker, faithfully applying the objectively ‘valid’ legal tests to the properly identified ‘material facts’ of the case, would have been compelled to arrive at the same conclusion. In other words, proper legal analysis must exemplify a type of judgement grounded in a ‘correct’ (that is conventional) identification of the ‘relevant’ law, combined with an equally ‘correct’ interpretation of its determinate meaning and scope of application. Liberalism thus portrays the reality of the legal system through the lens of its ideals of doctrinal ‘determinacy’; it thereby disregards the contrary insight of qualitative social scientific approaches to the legal process that routinely demonstrate the limits of the idea that the formal or paper rules concretely and fully determine legal outcomes.


According to Schmitt, an additional negative consequence stemming from how liberalism exaggerates doctrinal determinacy concerns the self-serving disguise of ideological manipulations of the language of legal devices, such as international treaties and conventions. Imperial states have an interest in exploiting linguistic indeterminacy of legal language, whilst at the same time denying this by claiming their practices are strictly following the letter of the law. For Schmitt, the United States articulates one aspect of its imperial power over international relations and law through its regular capacity to shape how semantic-interpretative issues are determined, and have these accepted as those of the ‘international community’ itself (Schmitt 1932/1988: 199).


Hence, forcing the ‘international community’ as articulated by the League of Nations, to accept the US Monroe Doctrine as a legitimate expression of international law, whilst reserving the interpretation of its main – yet highly ambiguous and open-ended – key terms to the United States alone, does not itself appear imperialistic. Instead, such semantic-rhetorical processes, rich in ideological potential and implications, are typically portrayed as a civilisational advance, a progressive measure of necessary reform and modernisation. Yet, Schmitt suggests that such disguised types of imperialistic practices are all the more effective for operating behind this semantic veil. Schmitt insists that the exploitation of, for example, the 1823 Monroe Doctrine’s linguistic indeterminacy, its ‘remarkable elasticity and vagueness, this leaving open all possibilities, including also the alternative of law and politics, is … typical of every true and great imperialism’ (Schmitt 1932/1988: 163; Ulmen 2003: 17 n 20).


This is a point that one of Schmitt’s commentators and – in part – leading exponents within contemporary international law scholarship, Martti Koskenniemi, has further developed. He characterises linguistic manipulation as a vital technique of US hegemonic control and possible contestation, as a concrete example of the friend/enemy distinction that Schmitt claims is characteristic of ‘the political’:



By hegemonic contestation I mean the process by which international actors routinely challenge each other by invoking legal rules and principles on which they have projected meanings that support their preferences and counteract those of their opponents. In law, political struggle is waged on what legal words such as ‘aggression’, ‘self-determination’, ‘self-defence’, ‘terrorist’ or ‘jus cogensmean, whose policy will they include, whose will they oppose? To think of this struggle as hegemonic is to understand that the objective of the contestants is to make their partial view of that meaning appear as the total view, their preference seems like the universal preference. There are many examples of this contestation. The process that led into the definition of aggression by the UN General Assembly in 1974 was about drawing a line between acceptable and unacceptable forms of coercion in a situation where different solutions put States in unequal positions. Every suggested definition seemed either underinclusive or overinclusive from some participant perspective, that is, covering cases one did not wish to cover (i.e. the behaviour of oneself or one’s ally) or not covering cases that should have been covered (i.e. forms of behaviour of foreseeable enemies). Everyone participated in the nearly 20-year process with two (understandable) objectives: to encompass as much as possible of the behaviour of one’s enemies while making sure that nothing would limit the freedom of action of one’s own country.


(Koskenniemi 2005: 119)


Schmitt suggests that scholars of international law need to connect ‘exception’/option clauses within such devices to the underlying geopolitical reality of power politics (including the protection from nationalisation of US investments) that are often strategically masked by the high-minded general terms, such as ‘non-intervention’, ‘self-determination’ and the ‘equality of all states’. In this respect, the ideological manipulation of linguistic indeterminacies specifically in relation to the question of ‘who decides?’ upon whether or not specific reservation clauses authorising military intervention apply, remains a perennial question of specific relevance to past and present forms of imperial power (Scheuerman 1999: 144–5). As Rasch notes: