Legal Doctrine: Which Method(s) for What Kind of Discipline?

As from the mid-nineteenth century, those conclusions have repeatedly led to the statement that ‘legal doctrine’ misses basic characteristics in order to be considered a ‘legal science’, whereas until then legal doctrine had largely been seen to be the model ‘science’.1 More recently, it is particularly the research assessment procedures and the repartition of public money among ‘scientists’ that have put this topic into the centre of the scholarly debate. Lawyers have reacted in different ways to this pressure. A large majority of them have pointed to the practical utility, and even necessity, of their publications for legal practice and emphasised the importance of law in society, or they have benignly ignored that criticism. Others have accepted the criticism, taking over the narrow empiricist view on ‘science’ and tried to make legal scholarship fit that model.2 In the nineteenth century, this kind of reaction gave birth to ‘legal theory’ in the sense of a ‘positive science of law’, a kind of empirical ‘natural law’, a search for legal concepts, legal rules and legal principles that the whole of mankind would share.3 There has been some research in legal anthropology (Maine, Post),4 but largely this remained at the stage of a research programme, which has been forgotten as from the First World War. Somewhat similar to this reaction, we have seen, as from the end of the nineteenth century, and mainly in the course of the twentieth century, the birth and development of other social sciences focusing on law: legal sociology, legal psychology, law and economics. All of those disciplines offer empirical research and theory building in legal matters. However, they never aimed at replacing legal doctrine, but just wanted to supply legal scholars, legal practitioners and policymakers with useful information on legal reality. Unfortunately, their impact has remained quite limited. So, today, there is a somewhat schizophrenic situation in which one discipline, legal doctrine, is basically studying law as a normative system, limiting its ‘empirical data’ to legal texts and court decisions, whereas other disciplines study legal reality, law as it is. The outcomes of these two strands of disciplines are not brought together in any systematic way, nor are they combined or integrated at the level of legal scholarship.


Today, in different countries, research assessment and the financial means connected with it have made the empiricist view on science even more influential. This has been to such an extent that it has made lawyers and policymakers in universities think that legal doctrine can only become ‘scientific’ if it turns into an empirical social science (de Geest). In other words, the aim is to put an end to a tradition of more than two millennia and to imitate the empirical sciences that have a different goal. Instead of concluding that the monist view on science, based on physics, is wrong, ‘falsified’ in their terminology, because it does not fit with disciplines such as legal doctrine, some have concluded that legal doctrine is (completely) wrong, and has always been so. This is a dangerous development, which, starting from false assumptions (unity and similarity of all scientific disciplines) is jeopardising the future of human sciences in general and legal doctrine in particular.


Of course, the criticism of legal doctrine is partly founded: it is often too descriptive, too autopoietic, without taking the context of the law sufficiently into account; it lacks a clear methodology and the methods of legal doctrine seem to be identical to those of legal practice; it is too parochial, limited to very small scientific communities, because of specialisation and geographical limits; there is not much difference between publications of legal practitioners and of legal scholars. All this may be correct, but as such it does not disqualify legal doctrine as a discipline in its own right, with its own, appropriate, methods.


In this chapter, I will define legal doctrine as an ‘empirical-hermeneutical discipline’. Indeed, it has empirical aspects, which make it perfectly comparable with all empirical disciplines, but the core business of legal doctrine is interpretation, which it has also in common with some other disciplines (theology, study of literature).


How can we describe the methodology of legal doctrine in a terminology which is largely used in the scientific community, without narrowing it in such a way that we lose essential characteristics of this discipline?


Legal doctrine has, in the course of history, been practised and conceived in varying ways, emphasising, and sometimes overemphasising, diverging characteristics of this discipline. Below, we will discuss the different angles from which legal doctrine has been presented and the extent to which they give a true picture of this discipline. It will be followed by an analysis of the methodology of legal research in terms of hypotheses and theory building.


II.  WHAT KIND OF DISCIPLINE IS LEGAL DOCTRINE?


A.  A Hermeneutic Discipline


It can hardly be denied that legal scholars are often interpreting texts and arguing about a choice among diverging interpretations. In this way, legal doctrine is a hermeneutic discipline, in the same way as is, for example, the study of literature, or to a somewhat lesser extent, history. Interpreting texts has been the core business of legal doctrine since it started in the Roman Empire.5


In a hermeneutic discipline, texts and documents are the main research object and their interpretation, according to standard methods, is the main activity of the researcher. This is clearly the case with legal doctrine.


Often legal scholarship has been presented as another type of ‘science’, in which the hermeneutic dimension is minimised, or at least made less important. This was done, for instance, when scholars tried to distinguish legal scholarship from legal practice, or to separate the description of the law more clearly from its evaluation, or when legal scholarship was modelled along the lines of the methodology of other disciplines and more specifically of the positive sciences.


B.  An Argumentative Discipline


Close to the conception of legal doctrine as a hermeneutic discipline is the conception of an argumentative discipline. Here, it is the argumentation to support some legal interpretation or solution that is emphasised, rather than the interpretation as such.6 The argumentative view has the advantage of putting things into a broader perspective. It allows us to take a step back from the interpreted text or any other document. A concrete legal question can be answered, or a case solved, on the basis of generally accepted, or at least acceptable, views. In traditional argumentation theory they are called ‘topoi’7. In many cases the argumentation will support some interpretation of one or more texts, but in other cases the argumentation may only loosely be related to such texts, eg when based on unwritten legal principles, or when filling gaps in the law, or when a text is simply put aside in favour of an interest or value that is considered to be more important.


From the Middle-Ages until the seventeenth century legal doctrine has developed as an argumentative discipline, which determined what kind of arguments were acceptable in which cases, with whole catalogues of arguments.8 Actually, interpretation and argumentation cannot be separated from each other, both in legal doctrine and in legal practice. Each text interpretation needs arguments when diverging interpretations could reasonably be sustained, and a legal argumentation will almost always be based on interpreted texts. So, legal doctrine and legal practice are both hermeneutic and argumentative, but interpretation and argumentation appear to be roughly two sides of the same activity, in which interpretation is the goal and argumentation the means for sustaining that interpretation. Hence, if one has to choose it would seem more appropriate to label legal doctrine a ‘hermeneutic discipline’ rather than an argumentative one.


C.  An Empirical Discipline


As already mentioned above, since the nineteenth century and under the influence of the success of the positive sciences, attempts have been made to develop legal scholarship as an empirical discipline.9 This has been quite explicitly worded by Alf Ross:



The interpretation of the doctrinal study of law presented in this book rests upon the postulate that the principle of verification must apply also to this field of cognition – that the doctrinal study of law must be recognised as an empirical social science.10


According to Ross, this empirical verification takes place by checking statements in legal doctrine against judicial practice: ‘Our interpretation, based on the preceding analysis, is that the real content of doctrinal propositions refers to the actions of the courts under certain conditions.’11


This view is typical for the realist movements. Ross was the last important representative of Scandinavian realism, but here Ross comes quite close to American realism: ‘The prophecies of what courts will do in fact, and nothing more pretentious, are what I mean by the law’, in the well known wording by Oliver Wendell Holmes.12 Ross’ conception of legal doctrine as an empirical discipline only fits in such a ‘realistic’ approach. Today, this realistic movement is not very popular in Europe, not even in Scandinavia. Hence, this conception of legal doctrine cannot be considered to be a workable model as such.


Others have argued that the phenomena which are observed and studied by legal scholars are in fact their empirical data and amount to ‘legal rules’.13 It is, however, to be questioned whether ‘legal rules’ can be observed empirically. If not, where and how do we find them? For Gerrit De Geest they are found through the reading of published judicial decisions. This view suggests that those rules only ‘exist’ to the extent that they have been applied by judges. In this way, De Geest is following Alf Ross and American realism. However, De Geest partly contradicts himself when defining the ‘empirical truth’ in interpreting the law as ‘what the legislator or judge really meant’.14 As methods used in this context, he mentions:



(a)  text analysis;


(b)  logic (eg syllogism);


(c)  field research (including interviews);


(d)  statistics; and


(e)  methods of historical research.15


It is interesting to note that no psychological methods are mentioned as a possible means to discover what a judge or legislator ‘really meant’. Without further discussing De Geest’s position here, it is obvious that his label ‘empirical research’ covers a large variety of elements, which show (also according to De Geest) that legal doctrine is partly a hermeneutic discipline (text analysis), an axiomatic discipline (logic) and a historical discipline. Indeed, legal doctrine cannot be reduced to one single type of discipline, but is a combination of several of them. Of course, some may be considered to be more important, or decisive, or typical than others, but, unlike some other disciplines, such as mathematics, it is not one-dimensional.


In Hans Albert’s view, the object of an empirical legal doctrine is broader than just legal rules. It also includes the influence of those rules on the members of the society in question.16 This means a combination of traditional legal doctrine with legal sociology. There are good reasons for such an approach, but putting it into practice seems to be very difficult in most cases. Moreover, one may also have to include other disciplines, such as economics, psychology and the like. However, including all this in legal doctrine raises even more questions as to its feasibility.


For the Historical School in nineteenth century Germany17 and a somewhat comparable movement in the United States in the same period,18 historical elements constituted the most important empirical data:



Man is to be studied in every period of his social existence, from the savage to the civilized state, in order to perceive the great truth, that in every condition of freedom, of intelligence, of commerce, and of wealth, his habits, his virtues, his vices, the objects of his desires, and hence the laws necessary for his government, are essentially the same.19


This approach clearly represents a belief in a kind of ‘natural law’ which could be retrieved empirically. This idea used to be quite popular in Europe and in the United States in the nineteenth century, but seems to have almost completely disappeared today.


For others, the object of the empirical research is sociological, economical or socio-psychological data, or more generally ‘human behaviour’.20


Empirical research is most notably useful in disciplines such as physics, where a reality is studied which exists independently of this discipline. In disciplines such as mathematics or theology, empirical research does not seem to be quite relevant. Mathematical models and theological views create their own reality, which, by definition, cannot be checked empirically. The same is largely true for legal doctrine as well. Whether a certain law ‘exists’ may be checked ‘empirically’, but what legal doctrine is mainly about is the interpretation of that law or its balancing with other laws or legal principles.


Interpretations are underpinned with arguments and these arguments may partly refer to an ‘objective’ reality. To this extent the correctness of arguments may be checked empirically. However, most arguments in legal reasoning are not ‘true’ or ‘false’ but more or less convincing. They do not qualify for an empirical verification.


D.  An Explanatory Discipline


A fourth conception of legal doctrine considers it to be an explanatory discipline. According to this view, legal doctrine explains why a rule is a valid legal rule in a given society. This explanation may be historical, sociological, psychological, economical and the like, but it may also be based on an internal logic. In this approach, the existence of a rule will be ‘explained’ by the existence of a higher norm, from which that rule is derived,21 or the existence of underlying values or principles, or of a larger network of legal rules and principles.


The first kind of explanation reduces legal doctrine to one or more of the social sciences involved. The second, internal, ‘explanation’ largely reduces this concept to something which is not even a main part of legal scholarly activity, and which does not really fit into our common understanding of what it means to ‘explain’ something. As Aleksander Peczenik wrote, we are rather faced with a veiled strategy in which presenting legal doctrine as an ‘explanatory’ discipline would allow us to consider it an ‘objective science’, and to conceal the legitimation of a rule behind a façade of ‘explanation’.22 In fact, nothing is ‘explained’ here, rather values or principles are postulated, or some interpretation of a higher rule is posited, which should legitimate the rule one derives from them.


Another view considers it the aim of legal scholarship to explain rule-determined behaviour,23 in interaction with other actors.24 However, this is rather the aim of legal sociology than of legal doctrine. Legal scholarship, in this approach, becomes a social technology.25


Explaining the whys and wherefores of legal concepts, rules, principles and constructions is indeed not an unimportant part of legal doctrinal research as it is necessary for interpreting them correctly. However, explanation is not the main content of research in legal doctrine, except maybe during some time following large-scale codifications. The hermeneutical and explanatory research activities are closely linked to each other, but explanation is at the service of interpretation, not the other way around. Hence, legal doctrine is not mainly an explanatory discipline.


E.  An Axiomatic Discipline


Legal doctrine has sometimes been seen in continental Europe as an axiomatic discipline, like mathematics. Gustav Hugo, one of the founders of the Historical School in nineteenth century Germany, worded it as follows:



Jurisprudenz und Mathematik grenzen auch näher an einander als mancher, der weder Jurist noch Mathematiker ist, weiss. . . . Auch die Jurisprudenz beruht in der Theorie auf einer Art von Construction und auch die Jurisprudenz ist in der Theorie eine exacte Wissenschaft.26


For Hugo, legal doctrine was an applied exact science, with also some empirical dimension. This approach to legal doctrine culminated in Germany at the end of the nineteenth century in the ‘Begriffsjurisprudenz’ movement, which saw law as an algebra of legal concepts.


In the second half of the twentieth century, this approach to legal doctrine had a revival, which, however, did not last long. Some optimists hoped to encompass the whole of law in a formal logic and/or in computer programmes which, up to now, did not prove to be very successful.


F.  A Logical Discipline


The view on legal doctrine as a logical discipline is a somewhat more moderate version of the pure axiomatic model:



In der Rechtsordnung spielt das Logische nur eine sekundäre Rolle neben den alogischen Momenten. In der Rechtsanwendung spielen diese alogische Momente die sekundäre Rolle neben dem Logischen. In der Rechtswissenschaft endlich herrschen ausschliesslich die logische Funktionen: die Jurisprudenz dient mit logischen Mitteln dem logischen Zwecke der Systematisierung.27