Introduction

1


Introduction


Contents


1.1    Overview


1.2    Introduction


1.3    Contractual theory


1.4    The classical law of contract


1.5    The subject matter of contract law


1.6    Discrete and relational transactions


1.7    Contract, tort and restitution


1.8    A law of contract or law of contracts?


1.9    Different approaches to analysing contract


1.10  International influences


1.11  Further reading




This chapter is divided into two sections:


First, there is a short introduction to the English law of contract, giving an indication of some of the main issues that arise for discussion in subsequent chapters. The second section undertakes a more thorough analysis of some of the theoretical issues that arise in discussing contract law.


In relation to contractual theory, the order of treatment is:


image    What is meant by the ‘classical’ law of contract? This refers to a body of rules, generally developed by nineteenth-century cases and the first contract textbook writers. It still has great influence in the modern law of contract.


image    What is the ‘subject matter’ of contract law? Is it simply a matter of enforcing promises, or is it concerned with regulating markets or facilitating trade? The ‘voluntary agreement’ seems to be at its heart.


image    Should contracts be looked at as ‘discrete’, isolated events, or are they part of a continuing relationship between the parties? The work of Macneil, in particular, suggests that a ‘relational’ analysis is more satisfactory in many situations.


image    How is ‘contract’ distinguished from other areas of law involving civil obligations, such as tort and restitution? The ‘voluntary exchange’ is one of the distinguishing factors.


image    How far is the law of contract governed by general principles, as opposed to specific rules applying to particular types of contract, such as sale of goods, employment, land, credit? It is argued that there is still room for general principles.


image    What techniques for the analysis of contract can be adopted? Consideration is given to:


image    doctrinal analysis (looking simply at cases and statutes);


image    socio-economic analysis (drawing on other disciplines to help explain the law); and


image    empirical research (investigating what happens in practice between contracting parties).


image    International influences on English contract law, including developments towards a European contract law.



The English law of contract is a ‘common law’ subject. This means that most of its rules and principles are derived from case law, and the application of the doctrine of precedent. There are, however, increasing areas that are affected by statutory provisions, and in particular regulations in the area of consumer contracts that derive from law emanating from the European Union.


The rules forming the English law of contract are, subject to the intervention by statute, applicable to all contracts. The rules of formation, for example, apply to a contract to buy some vegetables in a supermarket as much as to a million pound deal for the supply of goods and services between two multinational corporations. This universality can cause problems where very different types of contracts may have differing requirements, and do not fit easily into ‘one size fits all’ rules.


Contract law is, as is explained later in this chapter (1.5), concerned with the regulation of agreements, and in particular agreements to exchange goods and services for money or other goods or services (or both). Its obligations are generally voluntarily assumed, and on that basis it is distinguishable from the law of tort, which is concerned with obligations that are imposed by the law (e.g. to drive carefully).


What are the issues which arise in trying to regulate agreements, and which are therefore dealt with in more detail in the subsequent chapters of this text?


1.2.1 FORMATION


If agreements are being analysed, the courts need to have some rules for establishing when an agreement has been reached. English law does this not by using formalities in most cases, but by looking simply at what the parties said and did and seeing if these words and actions, viewed objectively, suggest that they had reached an agreement. In particular, courts will normally look for an offer by one party that has been unequivocally accepted by the other party.


Problems in this area can arise when the parties are contracting at a distance, by post or email. The delay in communications may mean that one party may have had a change of mind by the time its message is received, and there will be difficult questions relating to when exactly a communication takes effect.


The issues relating to formation are dealt with in Chapter 2.


1.2.2 ENFORCEABILITY


Just because the parties have made an agreement, this does not necessarily mean that it is legally enforceable. English law has a number of methods of deciding whether an agreement is legally binding, but the most important ones are the concept of ‘consideration’, and the requirement of an intention to create legal relations.


‘Consideration’ is a complex topic. It involves a requirement that if an agreement is to be enforced by the courts it must not be one-sided – a contract involves an exchange, and not a gift. In other words, both parties must be contributing something to the deal for it to be enforceable. For example, the contract may be for the transfer of goods in exchange for payment of a sum of money. In this case, the payment of the money would be the ‘consideration’ for the transfer of the goods. If the goods were to be handed over without any payment, this would be a gift, and would fall outside the scope of the law of contract. The courts have developed extensive rules as to what does and does not constitute valid consideration, which will make an agreement enforceable.


In general, attempts to vary an existing agreement must involve consideration if they are to be enforceable. In some limited circumstances a variation of an agreement may be enforceable where the other party has reasonably relied on a promise that the variation will take place – this is the doctrine of ‘promissory estoppel’.


Finally, in relation to enforceability, just because there is agreement and consideration does not mean that an agreement will in all cases be enforceable. There must also be an intention to create a legal enforceable agreement. A domestic agreement between husband and wife under which the husband agrees to pay for all the repairs to their house in exchange for the wife paying for all the food shopping may have the characteristics of offer, acceptance and consideration, but is unlikely to be intended to be legally enforceable. Commercial agreements will, however, normally be taken to be intended to create a legal relationship.


Issues of enforceability are dealt with in Chapter 3 (consideration and promissory estoppel) and Chapter 4 (intention to create legal relations).


1.2.3 CONTENTS OF THE CONTRACT


Once an agreement has been made, disputes may arise as to what exactly its terms were intended to be. Even if the agreement is in writing there may be arguments that it is not complete, and that other terms should be read into it, or implied. The courts are reluctant to add to agreements in this way, but will do so in certain carefully defined situations. In some circumstances, terms may be implied by statute, for example the Sale of Goods Act 1979.


There may also be arguments as to what exactly particular terms of the contract were intended to mean. Should the courts follow the literal meaning of the words, if there is evidence that something else was actually intended? Currently, the courts are taking the view that they should interpret terms of a contract in the light of all the factual circumstances, and should not be tied to the literal meaning. This flexibility has its advantages, but can cause problems of uncertainty.


A particular type of clause that can cause problems is the limitation or exclusion clause, whereby one party attempts to limit their liability if they break the contract. Such clauses may be entirely reasonable in many cases, but the courts will look at them very carefully, particularly where there is an imbalance in the bargaining power between the parties (as where a large business is attempting to exclude its liability to an individual consumer). They will want to be sure that the clause was properly incorporated into the contract (e.g. that the other party had appropriate notice) and that the clause does cover the situation that has arisen. In addition, most exclusion clauses will now be subject to statutory control in the form of the Unfair Contract Terms Act 1977 and the Unfair Terms in Consumer Contracts Regulations 1999. These invalidate some types of exclusion, particularly in consumer contracts, and make others enforceable only if they are found to be ‘reasonable’. For example, attempts to exclude liability for death or personal injury caused by negligence will always be invalid; attempts to exclude liability for other losses caused by negligence will only be valid if they are reasonable.


The terms of the contract are dealt with in Chapter 6 and exclusion clauses in Chapter 7.


1.2.4 REASONS FOR SETTING THE CONTRACT ASIDE


In some circumstances, a contract that has been validly formed will be set aside by the courts because it is found to have some defect. The circumstances that can lead to this are sometimes referred to as ‘vitiating factors’.


One example of a vitiating factor is where one party has been misled into making the contract, by relying on a false statement by the other party – that is, by a ‘misrepresentation’. A misrepresentation, even if made innocently, can lead to the contract being set aside. If the misrepresentation was made fraudulently or negligently, then compensation can be awarded. Misrepresentation is discussed fully in Chapter 8.


Sometimes a party will allege that they entered into the contract on the basis of a mistake, and that it should therefore be set aside. The courts are generally reluctant to accept this argument, but will do so if, for example, the contract relates to a cargo in a ship that, unknown to either party, had sunk before the contract was made. Where the other party is aware of the mistake (for example, where they have assumed a false identity in order to encourage the contract), the courts may be more receptive to arguments based on mistake, but still impose fairly restrictive rules as to when the remedy will be available. Mistake is dealt with in Chapter 9.


Issuing threats of violence or other illegal conduct to induce the other party to make a contract will fall into the heading of duress. If proved, the courts will set the contract aside. The concept of duress has been expanded in recent case law to cover, for example, threats of economic action (e.g. to go on strike). As long as the threat involves inappropriate and illegitimate pressure on the other party, it is potentially ‘duress’. This concept is dealt with in Chapter 10.


Related to duress is the concept of ‘undue influence’. This does not need any threat, but simply a relationship in which one party has influence over the other’s decisions, and uses that influence to persuade the person to enter into a contract. If inappropriate influence has been used, then the courts will not allow the contract to be enforced. Examples of situations of potential undue influence include bank manager over an elderly customer, solicitor over client, and, in some cases husband over wife. Particular problems can arise where a husband persuades his wife to use their home as security for a business loan from a bank. If the wife later seeks to set her agreement with the bank aside on the basis of her husband’s undue influence, can she do so? The courts have struggled to find the appropriate balance between the creditor (bank) and the security (wife) in such situations. The issues arising out of this area are dealt with in Chapter 11.


Clearly, the courts would not enforce a contract to commit murder. But this is only a very clear example of a more general rule that the courts will not enforce contracts that involve illegality, or are otherwise contrary to public policy. Difficulties can arise where a contract is on the face of it legal, but can only be performed by one or both parties acting illegally – for example, a contract to buy alcohol, where the seller’s licence has expired. The rules for deciding when the courts should set the agreement aside are not always applied consistently, and some of the case law is difficult to reconcile. Illegality is dealt with in Chapter 12.


1.2.5 FRUSTRATION


Sometimes a contract cannot be completed because of circumstances outside the control of either party. For example, the contract is to redecorate a house, and between the making of the contract and performance starting, the house burns down. Where such an event happens, the contract is said to be ‘frustrated’ and both parties are absolved from future obligations. The main issues in frustration relate to deciding what kind of circumstances are sufficiently serious to frustrate the contract, and in sorting out the effects of frustration. The latter issue is affected by the provisions of the Law Reform (Frustrated Contracts) Act 1943.


Frustration is dealt with in Chapter 13.


1.2.6 PERFORMANCE, BREACH AND REMEDIES


If a party wishes to be paid for their performance of a contract, then they will need to show that they have completed the performance of their obligations under it. Issues may arise as to what constitutes complete performance, and when the other party is entitled to withhold payment until further work is done.


Where a contract has been broken, the party not in breach may seek to terminate the contract. Whether this is possible will depend on the seriousness of the term broken – was it a major term of the contract? In all cases, damages will be recoverable for losses that can be demonstrated to have been caused by the breach, subject to rules relating to ‘remoteness’ (was the loss one that could reasonably be expected to have followed from the breach) and ‘mitigation’ (did the party not in breach take all reasonable steps to limit the loss). Most contract damages will be for economic losses, including lost profits, but in some circumstances damages will be recoverable for non-pecuniary losses (for example, personal injury), including, exceptionally, disappointment and mental distress.


An order to perform a contract (‘specific performance’) is discretionary, and will not generally be awarded in relation to straightforward commercial transactions, where the payment of damages will constitute an adequate remedy.


Performance, breach and remedies are dealt with in Chapters 14 and 15.



The issues considered in the rest of this chapter are principally concerned with identifying the theoretical bases for the law of contract – what is it, and what is its scope? There are a number of possible approaches to these questions.


It might be asked, for example, what relationships the courts currently regard as being within the scope of the law of contract. Answering this relatively easy question might be of some use, particularly from the practical point of view of deciding how to deal with a dispute between A and B, and whether the courts would be likely to treat it as a contract. The task would, however, be essentially descriptive. If we want to go further and analyse the nature of contract or the contractual relationship, we will need to ask why some situations rather than others are dealt with as contractual, and try to find some rational basis for distinguishing between ‘contract’ and ‘non-contract’. This is an issue that has been the subject of regular academic discussion over the last 50 years.1 Moreover, even texts aimed at practitioners are unable to ignore it. Chitty on Contracts, the most well-established practitioner’s text, has an introductory chapter dealing with the ‘nature of contract’. Its more recently published rival, Furmston’s The Law of Contract,2 goes even further, including a lengthy first chapter on ‘General Considerations’ (written by Professor Roger Brownsword).3


Our starting point is the concept of the ‘classical law of contract’, which many would regard as still the dominant approach, certainly within the decisions of the courts on contractual issues.



It is generally accepted in modern writings on the English law of contract that during the latter half of the nineteenth century a concept of contract developed, together with an associated body of legal doctrine, which is now referred to as the ‘classical law of contract’. This is not necessarily a matter of precise historical accuracy. As Wightman has pointed out,4 the concept of the classical law can be said to be ‘invented’ in two senses. First, although based on decisions of the courts, the synthesis of those decisions into a (more or less) coherent body of law was largely the work of the ‘treatise writers’,5 whose work decided which cases would be given prominence, and who encouraged the formulation of principles of general application to a wide range of transactions. Second, the recognition of the model of contract law which emerged from the latter part of the nineteenth century as ‘classical’, with the intention of using that model as the basis for an argument that the requirements of ‘modern’ contract law were different and that adherence to the classical model was inhibiting its development, is largely the product of the work started by commentators writing in the 1970s.6


Whatever the accuracy of the precise historical origins of the classical theory, it is now generally accepted that it is centred around the concept of ‘freedom of contract’, probably as a reflection of the dominance in the nineteenth century of laissez-faire economic attitudes. At a time of swift industrialisation and increasing commercialisation of society, the best way of allowing wealth to develop was to let those involved in business regulate their own affairs, with the courts simply intervening to settle disputes. The parties to a contract will be governed by rational self-interest,7 and giving effect to transactions which result from this will be to the benefit of both the parties and society.


‘Freedom of contract’ in this context has two main aspects.8 The first is that it is the individual’s choice whether or not to enter into a contract, and if so with whom – in other words, the freedom to contract, or ‘party freedom’. The second is the freedom to decide on the content of the contractual obligations undertaken, or ‘term freedom’. This allows parties to make unwise, and even unfair, bargains – it is their decision, and the courts will not generally intervene to protect them from their own foolishness.


The paradigmatic contract which emerges from the classical theory has the following characteristics:



























(a) It is based on an exchange of promises.
(b) It is executory. This means that the contract is formed, and obligations under it arise, before either side has performed any part of it.
(c) It involves an ‘exchange’, so that each side is giving something in return for the other’s promise. It is the existence of this mutuality (given effect through the doctrine of ‘consideration’)9 which generally gives rise to enforceability.10
(d) The content of the contractual obligations is determined by deciding what the parties agreed, or what reasonable parties in their position would have agreed, at the time the contract was made. Later developments are of no significance.
(e) Disputes about a contract can generally be determined by asking what the parties expressly or impliedly agreed (or should be taken to have agreed) in the contract itself. This is sometimes referred to as the ‘will theory’ of contract.
(f) The transaction is discrete, rather than being part of a continuing relationship.
(g) The role of the court is to act as ‘umpire’ or ‘arbiter’, giving effect to the parties’ agreement. In particular, it has no role in deciding whether or not the transaction is ‘fair’.

There is probably also an underlying assumption that the parties are of equal bargaining power.


The type of contract that most closely fits the above paradigm is probably the commercial contract for the sale of goods, where the buyer and seller agree that at some agreed date they will exchange the ownership of goods of a specified type for a specified sum of money. In practice, however, most contracts are not of this kind, and attempts to apply to them rules which were designed to be suitable for the paradigmatic case are likely to produce tensions and problems. Nevertheless, the classical theory of contract, and its model of the typical contract, can still be seen to cast its shadow over English law. In the latter part of the twentieth century it was the subject of sustained attack by academic commentators, and many judicial decisions can be seen to have moved, in practice at least, from the strict classical formulations. There is still, however, a reluctance to abandon them, and it is frequently the case that the courts, when involved in a development away from the classical model, will continue to use language which suggests that they are being faithful to it.11 The challenge for the student of the modern law of contract in England is to reconcile the fact that it is still rooted in classical theory, at least in the way in which its concepts are expressed, while at the same time developing away from it. This is the reason why this book has adopted a format and chapter division which is largely traditional. It is within this traditional framework that the courts continue to consider contract cases. The substance of many of their decisions, however, and virtually all the interventions of Parliament, are taking the law in new directions. The form may be ‘classical’, but the content is ‘modern’, and this tension must be kept in mind in considering all that follows.


With this background to the development of the English law of contract in mind, we can now turn to the question of what exactly is meant by the ‘law of contract’. What is its scope, and what are its boundaries?



What is the law of contract about? This is a question to which, perhaps surprisingly, there is no clear, universally accepted answer. There are, however, several candidates for the basis of the legal enforceability of contractual obligations. They can be viewed, for example, as a means of:















(a) enforcing promises; or
(b) regulating the market in the provision of goods and services; or
(c) facilitating exchanges (for example, of goods or services for money).

Any of these individually, or some combination of them, can be put forward as being at the root of the law of contract, but none of them is without difficulty.


As we have seen, the idea of the ‘promise’ is central to the classical law of contract, and some modern commentators are happy to continue to regard this as its distinguishing feature. Burrows, for example, asserts that ‘The law of contract is concerned with binding promises. It looks at what constitutes a binding promise and how such a promise is made; at the remedies for breach of such a promise; and at who is entitled to those remedies.’12 There are, however, severe limitations to an interpretation of contract based on promises. Although some contracts are clearly made by the exchange of promises – for example, ‘I promise to build a house for you in accordance with these plans in exchange for your promising to pay me £100,000 on completion of the work’ – there are many that do not easily fit this model. In particular, as has been pointed out judicially by Lord Wilberforce, many everyday transactions, such as buying goods in a shop or travelling by bus, do not do so without considerable strain.13 They can be accommodated at best by taking the view that there is an implicit promise involved – for example, that the bus is travelling on the route indicated by its signboard. But in some situations it is difficult to find even a promise of this kind. In the typical shop transaction, a person takes goods to a till and hands over money. The contract has the effect of transferring the ownership of the goods from the seller to the buyer and of the money from the buyer to the seller. What promises are involved in a one-off transaction of this kind, which may well be conducted without any communication between the participants, and indeed increasingly frequently by using a ‘self-service’ till? The only one that can be identified is that the seller is implicitly ‘promising’ that the goods are of a satisfactory quality. However, since the obligation to supply goods which are satisfactory is imposed by statute and cannot be avoided in a consumer contract,14 it is not necessary to use the language of ‘promises’ to explain this aspect of the transaction.


Even in commercial transactions, as the case in which Lord Wilberforce made the statement quoted above demonstrated, there are also some situations where contractual rights and liabilities are assumed to exist, but it is difficult to see that there has been any making of promises. The parties in the case that Lord Wilberforce was discussing assumed that stevedores unloading goods from a ship would have the benefit of an exemption clause contained in a contract between the owners of the goods and the carriers. No explicit promise of this kind was made to the stevedores, however. Indeed, in contracts of this type, the identity of the stevedores might well be unknown at the time the contract was entered into. The court resolved this effectively by ‘imputing’ a promise from the owners to the stevedores, via the agency of the carriers, that they would have the benefit of the clause.15


On the other hand, there are clearly some situations where promises are at the heart of the contractual obligation. Contracts for the purchase and sale of commodities on the futures market plainly depend on the assumption that promises will be kept or that, if broken, compensation will be payable. Another example is the doctrine of promissory estoppel,16 which is based on the fact that it requires a person who makes a promise to be held to it, even though there is no consideration given for it.


The conclusion must be, therefore, as Brownsword has pointed out, that although it is possible to use ‘promise’ as a necessary definition of contract, this is only so if we include ‘express, implicit and imputed promises’.17 ‘Promise’ is not a sufficient condition, however, since there are situations in which clear and explicit promises are not enforced. In general, for example, promises that are neither supported by consideration nor contained in a deed will not generally be treated as binding on the promisor.18 In other areas where apparently gratuitous promises have been held to be binding, such as in the case of Williams v Roffey Bros & Nicholls (Contractors) Ltd,19 the courts have been at pains to find ‘consideration’, even if this has involved ‘stretching’ this concept so as not to be seen to be departing from the orthodoxy that gratuitous promises are not binding.


Furthermore, there are agreements that appear to have all the hallmarks of the archetypal classical contract – that is, an exchange of promises and consideration – which will nevertheless not be treated as binding. This may arise where there is no ‘intention to create legal relations’.20 This may be because the arrangement has been made in a domestic context.21 It can also arise, however, in a commercial context where it has been made clear that the agreement is ‘binding in honour only’.22 In both types of case, the courts are giving effect to what they see as being the intentions of the parties. This area, as an element in the formation of the contractual obligation, is discussed at length in Chapter 4. It is another indication, however, that a ‘promise’ is not in itself sufficient as a basis for identifying contractual obligations.


The second suggested candidate as the basis for modern contract law – market regulation – clearly has some force, in that part of what the courts do in developing and applying the law is to determine the limits of the free market. It does not, however, deal very satisfactorily with the situations where in fact the courts do not intervene to ‘regulate’ but simply give effect to what the parties themselves have agreed (or are deemed to have agreed) – even if the result may appear ‘unfair’ and provide no benefit to the general public.23 The courts in such a situation will not hold back from enforcing a ‘bad bargain’. Nevertheless, some commentators do see market regulation as being at the heart of contract law. Collins, for example, sees the ‘social market’ as being central to the modern law of contract.24 He sees three themes – ‘concern about unjustifiable domination, the equivalence of exchange, and the need to ensure co-operation’ – as forming the core of his interpretation of the law of contract.25 It might, of course, alternatively be argued that simply enforcing agreed obligations is to the general benefit, because it reduces transaction costs if the parties are aware that a clear agreement will be enforced, no matter that ‘injustice’ to one of the parties may result. This is the argument that ‘certainty’ in the law overall is preferable to ‘fairness’ on the facts of any particular case.


The third candidate identified above as a concept that might be said to be at the centre of contract is ‘exchange’, and this is at first sight an attractive proposition. Many of the transactions that we think of as involving a contract – for example, the purchase of goods or services – do involve ‘exchange’. A person transfers the ownership of goods to another in exchange for the price; work is done in exchange for wages; a company agrees to license the use of a patented process in exchange for royalties. There are, however, situations which do not properly involve an exchange, but which are nevertheless treated as contracts. First, there are those transfers of property that are effected by a formal deed. In this case, provided that the formalities of the deed are properly carried out, the transaction can be entirely gratuitous: nothing is required from the recipient to make the transaction legally binding. Such transactions are regarded as being within the province of contract law, and therefore need to be accommodated within any definitional scheme intended to delineate its scope.


It might, perhaps, be possible to treat transfers by deed as being an example of categorisation error, and to argue that they should be treated as sui generis and not part of the general law of contract. This would not solve the problem, however, since there are other situations which do not involve any proper exchange which it would be much more difficult to ‘hive off’ in this way. As we will see later,26 in informal contracts,27 although the law of contract normally requires a degree of ‘mutuality’, so that something is being provided by each party to the agreement, the value of what is being provided is generally irrelevant. Thus, suppose a rich aunt decides to make her favourite nephew, who is currently 19 years old, a gift of her Porsche on his 21st birthday. She could commit herself to this transaction by promising that she will transfer the car on the day of his birthday provided that he pays her one penny in exchange. The reality of this transaction is that she is making a gift of the car, and her nephew is providing nothing of real value in exchange. Nevertheless, the courts would treat this as a binding contract (subject to their being satisfied that there was an intention to create legal relations). The application of this approach in a more commercial context can be illustrated by the case of Chappell & Co Ltd v Nestlé Co Ltd,28 where the provision of the wrappers from bars of chocolate was held to be part of the consideration for the supply of a gramophone record. This was the case even though the wrappers were worthless and were thrown away by the company when received. The transaction had the trappings of exchange, but was in essence a ‘free gift’. Nevertheless, it was treated as contractual.


The reason for this relates to the fact that the courts are generally keen to adopt an approach that complies with the intention of the parties. If the parties, knowing the English law of contract, have used the trappings of exchange to clothe a transaction that is in effect a gift, they have probably done so in order to make their agreement legally enforceable, without going to the trouble of using a deed. The courts should therefore be prepared to give effect to that intention and treat the transaction as a binding contract.




For Thought


Why did Nestlé want people to send in the wrappers? What benefit was there to Nestlé in this promotion? Could this have been sufficient to constitute consideration?


We can, therefore, if we exclude contracts made by deed, argue for ‘exchange’ as being at the heart of contract. But here, similar to the way in which with the notion of ‘promise’ we needed to include implied, imputed and constructed promises, we will need to include ‘sham’ exchanges in order to make the approach work. And if we do that, we may well feel that we have still not really got very near to the essence of what makes a ‘contract’.

Only gold members can continue reading. Log In or Register to continue