Crossing


Chapter 1
Crossing



“The law, therefore, is a never-ending story”,


Luhmann, 2004:184




The horizon in the piazza


A book that presents Niklas Luhmann as a critical legal thinker is like a Giorgio de Chirico painting. The inappropriateness of the parallelism is blatant: de Chirico is the founder of the metaphysical school of painting; Luhmann has no time for metaphysics. De Chirico professed to be a constantly metamorphing god – philosopher – novelist – sculptor – painter – mythological personage – critic – surrealist – classicist – Italian – Greek – metaphysician; Luhmann professed sternly and unflinchingly to be a sociologist. De Chirico famously finds reality intolerable and is in constant pursuit of ‘another reality’; Luhmann consistently refers to the futility of trying to imagine ‘another’ reality. The list can go on with various degrees of simplification. It serves, however, the purpose of showing that it is as improbable to put Luhmann and ‘critical’ together, as it is to put Luhmann and de Chirico together.


And the result of such a fusion is in fact not unlike the de Chirico painting on the cover of this book. De Chirico’s metaphysical period is filled with dream landscapes: at first instance, a characteristic Italian piazza, empty but for its arches, statues and elongated shadows. The disorientation comes afterwards, when one realises that the arches flanking the piazza end up in different vanishing points; the statue in the middle looks as if seen from below; the figures in the background float about in an immaterial void, unconnected to the rest; the edges of the city stop abruptly and give way to expanses that reflect a collapsing sky. Juxtaposed architectural structures and dehumanised figures, palimpsestic temporal zones, non-causal perspectives, surfaces, light sources and shadows: all strictly confined in a claustrophobic canvas. But, and this is where the antithesis comes forcefully in, this very claustrophobia reserves its pivotal space for an all-commanding horizon, the ‘environment’ of an otherwise hermetically closed piazza.1 The effect of bringing forth the horizon through the grounded horizon-blocking structures is precisely the aim of the book: a trompe l’oeil that conflates structure and horizon, description and critique. Indeed, trying to balance Luhmann’s perspectival acrobatics with a space of critique requires considerable dosages of horizon in an otherwise seemingly solid piazza – and this is what this book attempts to do.


This book reads Luhmann through and against Luhmann – it constructs Luhmann’s constructions according to Luhmannian tools and exposes them to their internal horizon. Although Luhmann’s texts have often been (superficially, I hasten to add) read as a positivist, dry and conservative account of society, they will hopefully be revealed here to be nothing short of a labyrinth of elusive vantage points in constant contrast to a horizon of ‘transcendental’ opportunities – except that transcendence can only be already found within the fluctuating confines of the piazza. But how can the horizon fit in a piazza? Pictorially speaking, this is the paradox that this book attempts to tease out: the ‘enigma’ (to use de Chirico’s favourite term) that trails the distance between, on the one hand, law’s location in society, and, on the other, the paradoxes of law and their painstaking and almost compulsive hiding, dissimulating, postponing, burying. In other words, the present text tries to render visible the continuum and simultaneous rupture (the enigma of presence and absence that is everywhere in Luhmann) between the paradox and its utterances. It has to be said, however, that it does not perform anything that is not already there in Luhmann’s texts, in full readiness to be brought forth. The book does not constitute a critique of Luhmann but a critical reading of Luhmann’s text. In that sense, I do not assume a different, ‘critical’ position from which I read Luhmann’s texts; on the contrary, I position myself well in the thick of the various edifices, immanently describing and playing with the various contingencies on offer. In so doing, this text moves around: in the centre of the square, underneath the arches or closer to the shadow of the passer-by. It changes perspectives, thus engendering different vistas and allowing the space to be observed in an occasionally surprising light. Ultimately, the space is inverted, turned inside out, subsequently only to return to its starting point of apparent ‘normality’. Again, this is not a conservative point: on an abstract level, it is an attempt at anchoring the kind of critique performed in this book; on a legal level, it is the awareness of law’s societal function and location; and on a textual level, it is a return of the present text to Luhmann’s texts despite critical perambulations. The latter return does not serve as a guarantee of authenticity or, worse, as a manifestation of the desire to maintain things as they are. Rather, the return is the precondition for a rereading, or better, for a continuous reading, interrupted only by the act of reading itself.



The possibilities of escape from the painting or indeed from the text are inscribed within each of them in the shape of the horizon. ‘Horizon’ here is understood simply as yet another space that enables distinctions. A distinction distinguishes between persevering and escaping, here and there, this and that, now and then. It is not another, ‘better’ place to which one should take refuge, but a platform on which such places can be imagined while remaining, and this is perhaps the crux of the paradox, immanent. As its etymology reveals, horizein is to separate and to delimit. The horizon disturbs, fragments, hides, reveals: in short, it distinguishes. Itself an immanent possibility of another space, and simultaneously the limit of an all-containing space, the horizon is an invitation to be crossed. The horizon only appears at conditions of lucid atmosphere, clear light, bright skies: all conditions that feed an illusion of total clarity. But by appearing in this luminous geography where hubris circles overhead, the horizon shutters any illusions of theological überobservation and reveals the limits of the eye. Along the horizon comes the fear, “a fear we experience in the face of total intellectual lucidity, when all answers are known”:2 a fear to lose that knowledge, a fear to cross over that knowledge and encounter its illusion, or a fear that this crossing brings the fall. The appearance of the horizon, in both de Chirico and Luhmann, is an invitation to escape and simultaneously an (always returning) invitation to fail in one’s escape.3 The two blur into an indistinguishable form and what remains is the irrepressible clarity of the invitation to cross to the other side. This crossing, in its paradoxical success and failure, I would describe as ‘critique’.




A critical crossing


To begin critically entails a departure. It also entails an (illusion of) arrival. In this sense, critique actualises itself in the crossing of a boundary. In this movement from one side to the other of the boundary, critique performs its krinein, its distinguishing, indicating and judging.4 Thus, a legal critique begins from the current state of the law and crosses the boundary that distinguishes the latter from a ‘better’state of the law. In its urge to cross, critique announces a crisis (a judgement, a distinction), a crisis of crossing (critique cannot leave itself out) as well as a crisis than can only be observed through this crossing. A critical crossing is a flirtation with improbability but from the (critical) point of probability – for why else would one embark on a critical crossing if the illusion of arrival were not at least convincingly entertained?



The above formulation poses some seemingly insurmountable problems for this book. To start with, Luhmann was notoriously anti-critique, anti-crisis and in a certain sense, anti-crossing. Following this, any presentation and discussion of Luhmann’s work has to respect a foundational Luhmannian replacement: prescription is replaced by description.5 The question, therefore, is whether there is room for critique in description. The difference between prescription and description for the purposes of a critical crossing is that in the latter no arrival is posited other than the very point of origin – in other words, in description there is always a return that follows any oscillating excursus. Simply put, a description of a suggested destination would be a prescription in the sense of a call to departure. But a description that does not arrive anywhere else than to itself is itself an autological destination that contains no departure. Within description, the destination is not prescribed. At most it is forecast, but then only as an altered state of the present and without any desire (to depart, to reach, to imagine). Herein lies description’s apparent negation of critique. It has to be said, however, that this negation is not in the sense of a lack of a different place from which to describe: indeed, Luhmannian description entails precisely this kind of departure from the usual mode of description, with the paradoxical consequence of both pluralising and annulling perspectives. Thus, description does not mean the impossibility of imagining other perspectives, other places. Rather, it indicates an unwillingness to imagine a better place which can operate as destination, in view of the impossibility of comparing the various places.


This is because, according to Luhmann, there is no other place: “one can today formulate a theory of postmodernity or act out one’s aversions to the factually supporting structures of our social system. Since, however, modern society is, and continues to be, factually without alternatives, there is little sense in semantically resorting to irrelevance in such a way.”6 Indeed, post-modernity is for Luhmann ‘mere’semantics without any purchase on ‘structure’ or ‘factuality’,7 “a belated recognition of the contingency of modernity.”8 As he says, quoting Bateson,9 postmodernity is a difference (distinction) that does not actually make a difference: all the elements that are traditionally diagnosed as postmodern have been around for longer. Thus, the absence of grand narratives or metanarratives in the Lyotardian sense10 can be readily found in Luhmann’s concept of functional differentiation, namely the arbitrary point of differentiation amongst the various societal systems, such as law, politics, religion, economy and so on, and the consequent disappearance of any vantage point from which one ideologically imposing description of society could emerge.11 By the same token, the loss of the binding force of tradition “is so old that it has itself become a tradition.”12 It seems therefore that postmodernity is a way for society to describe itself, which has no other effect except the presentation of an ‘alternative’ unity of society to itself. This is what Luhmann means when he writes “[society] can distinguish itself and describe itself, using a few operations to produce self-descriptions. For instance, it can say ‘we’. It can refer to itself by a name … The self-designation of ‘modern’ or ‘postmodern’ society belongs to this category.”13 It would seem, then, that postmodernity for society is a necessary illusion that denotes an alternative space within itself from which to describe and potentially criticise itself. But Luhmann seems to have much less patience with this necessary illusion than with other identity (namely self-description) formations, as I show below.14 This may be attributed to the fact that Luhmann’s theories can indeed be read as distinctly postmodern.15 The aforementioned characteristics of lack of metanarratives and detraditionalisation are central to it, combined with a consistent return to unsolvable paradoxes, a post-humanist orientation and an acentric societal organisation. All of them are described without ever losing sight of the impossibility of describing anything with any certainty in view of an uncontainable and ultimately unpredictable contingency. So this may sound distinctly ‘postmodern’. Still, Luhmann’s position is not that easily located and fixed. Compare the above with another Luhmannian habit: Luhmann regularly talks the language of ‘the’ system (while digging from within), flirts with (while uprooting) traditional dogmatics, appropriates (while altering beyond recognition) the thoughts of thinkers – in short, Luhmann constructs a modernity which turns as it were against itself by revealing itself in colours not easily soothed by illusionary constructions of identity, but only through an acceptance of the return to the paradox: “in view of all the fine prospects offered to Dr. Johnson in Scotland, there may be only one that is really attractive – the way back to England, the way back to the origin, the way back to the paradox.”16 Call it whatever you will, but society is all there is and the return to its paradoxes is the only thing that cannot be avoided, Luhmann says. And choosing to disregard this all-inclusion leads to a well-known type of critique: “The distinction between affirmative and critical, a distinction so beloved in Frankfurt … excludes the possibility that what has become realized as society gives cause for the worst fears, but cannot be rejected.17 The continuous rejection of the object of critique (which coincides with the source of one’s worst fears) ends up in a neurosis of the kind Luhmann has often diagnosed in Habermas.18 The debate between the two is perhaps one of the better-known and documented parts in Luhmann’s academic career,19 and perhaps the least useful to a critical (in the present sense) understanding of his theory. Luhmann’s talk at a conference on the enduring presence and relevance of the Frankfurt School ended in a typically provocative way: to the self-posed question “whether, and how, modern society at the end of this century can achieve a representation of itself in itself (where else?)”, Luhmann answered, “my verdict is: not in Frankfurt.”20 In the same way, if the arrogance is forgiven, I would answer the self-posed question on whether there is any point in returning to the Luhmann-Habermas debate, with a copycat “not in this book”.21 Although a brief and indirect exposition of some of their differences appears immediately below, this is not the kind of critique in which I am interested. For that kind of critique, distinctions between society and its ‘outside’, horizon and piazza, immanence and escape, and above all law and justice, are more relevant and indeed appear throughout the text. Consequently, in what follows the immediate need to locate critique amidst society’s all-inclusiveness is addressed, which consists the epistemological stance of the book while also revealing Luhmann’s location in contemporary epistemology.


While a description of what Luhmann means by society is reserved for later,22 here I want to start with the deceptively simple presupposition that if society is all there is, then there is no place for critique of society except within society. Society’s all-inclusiveness has been seen as co-opting of critique in the form of the inevitability that links ‘is’ and ‘ought’,23 confounding thus the limits of society with a perceived absence of limitations. Luhmann sees this as normal occurrence in a society that observes itself: “every observation of society – if actualised as communication – occurs within society. The critique of society is part of the system that it criticises: it lets itself be inspired and subsidised, observed and described.”24 Namely, if society is all there is and any critique addresses (parts or the whole of) society, then critique is part of it too; what is more, it is a part that can be seduced or even co-opted by its object (“inspired and subsidised”). This would be a rather banal position if it were not further elaborated: in a semi-targeted outburst against (Frankfurt) critique, Luhmann questions the privileged point that critique (and more specifically critical sociology) assumes in order to perform what is expected of it. In a Luhmannian world where no perspective is anything more than just that – one perspective that could always be other – critique is an almost theological affront that allows itself the illusion of “irreproachable moral impulses” and “the best perspective”.25 This perspective seems to enable observation (and announcement) of crisis, not only in terms of diagnosis but also of healing. And a crisis, faithful to its Greek origins of judgement, contains the other side too, the one that has already been prioritised as the better one. Crisis is mount on the presupposition, not only that there is, but that “there must be – as it were – a good society behind society, towards which to redirect structures and effects in order to arrive to a better future.”26 Sweeping or not, this critique of critique addresses a well-known fetishisation of the other better place while attempting to move away from the “grand bourgeois tradition of crisis and critique” whose consequence remains “the constant production of dissent with a view to a rational understanding.”27


Luhmann dismisses both rationality and dissent as illusions. The pursuit of rationality is perhaps the greatest problem inherited from Enlightenment on account of both its instrumentality and its anthropocentricity;28 dissent, on the other hand, always speaks from within, and although potentially relevant, it has to be conceptualised precisely in its immanence in order to be meaningfully understood.29 For this reason, Luhmann insinuates an understanding of critique as observation. While I return to this fundamental concept later, it is important to note that Luhmann differentiates between two kinds of observation: first- and second-order observation. First-order observation focuses on what others observe; second-order on how others observe. Second-order observation is emphatically not a critique30 – it is simply another perspective, without pretences of überobservation, that raises the complexity of the process of observation thus attempting to produce adequately complex observations that would adequately describe a complex society. Professing to operate consistently in the mode of second-order observation, Luhmann contends that his perspective is not a better one,31 simply another one that can always be other. But there is awareness of this contingency, and this is precisely on account of the second-order level of observation: observing how others observe means that a second-order observer can also observe what a first-order observer cannot observe (importantly, of the choice that the first-order observer has made).32 Indeed, if a first-order observer distinguishes between observed and non-observed, a second-order observer observing the first-order observer can see both sides of the distinction (no doubt while creating further distinctions). At the same time, the second-order observer can always be observed from a different standpoint and variously as first- or second-order observer. In this sense, observation is the tool that delivers Luhmann from both objectivism and subjectivism.33


Luhmann has built his theoretical edifice on the premises of second-order observation. Second-order does not mean value-free or ‘objective’ (in the same way that first-order does not mean ‘subjective’). Terminological incompatibilities aside, the distinction between first- and second-order observation reproduces several philosophical and psychoanalytical schemata, but perhaps more relevantly that of Husserlian epoche. Epoche is the bracketing of the ‘natural’ world (the ‘natural attitude’) for the ‘transcendental attitude’. The idiom of the ‘transcendental attitude’ originates in the distance from the everyday world and the departure for another level of observation,34 or as Luhmann puts it in the context of second-order observation, “a distance from immediately fact-related observations and distinctions … a second level, on which one can observe and describe observations and descriptions themselves.”35 This level is not ‘higher’ but merely more complex because it requires the application of further distinctions: between observer and observed, between observed and non-observed, between observed and act of observation.36 The second-order observer, riding the distance between first-and second-order, applies another distinction on the already existing first-order distinction, thus contextualising and debilitating it. What appears as a value in first-order observation, it becomes pluralised and diluted according to its definitional horizon.37 Second-order observation refuses indulging the illusion of a privileged point of description (of critique of ideology), and conditions any such tendencies by an awareness of self-contingency – something that first-order observation distinctly lacks since it cannot enter a comparison of position between itself and another.


As mentioned, however, Luhmann does not equate the distance afforded by second-order observation with a critical stance. Second-order observation is still within the operations of factuality whose products are routinely employed by the various observers in order to carry on observing.38 This is possibly the reason for which Luhmann insists on the redundancy of deconstruction in the face of the already practiced second-order observing.39 Just as postmodernity, deconstruction does not do anything substantially more than second-order observation. On the contrary, Luhmann maintains albeit with less conviction, deconstruction remains on the level of semantics, whereas second-order observation engages with structure. It is, however, difficult to accept this division and consign either of the two practices to one side.40 As Urs Stäheli correctly finds, semantics in Luhmann (at least in his later writings, I would add) is used as “a polemical device for marking theoretical positions … e.g. turning ‘postmodernism’ into a problem of semantics, helps to distance [Luhmann’s] theory from competing theories by implying that a concept may be pure semantics, i.e., without any reference to reality.”41 This device is, I believe, one of the least attractive aspects of the theory, and for this reason I agree with Stäheli when he writes that it would need a “serious re-working”.42 The fact that any discussion, let alone ‘serious re-working’ of Luhmann’s distinction between semantics and structure exceeds the ambit of this book is merely one reason for which I shall not engage with it. The other, perhaps more important reason has to do with the fact that it is difficult to read such passages by Luhmann and not discern both a defensiveness and what I would dare characterise an envy in Luhmann. His attempts at showing how second-order observation has already ‘done’ deconstruction ‘and more’, are to some extent convincing, but ultimately irrelevant to the present discussion on account of their limited exegetic interest and their somewhat arbitrary distinctions. Nevertheless, as Luhmann admits, “deconstruction will survive its deconstruction as the most pertinent description of the self-description of modern society.”43 For me this is enough of a licence to explore, when relevant, the parallels without residing on their supposed levels of operation. For it is after all the case that, in following Luhmann, whatever I do I merely describe.


Thus, critique remains a description – hence its distance from Frankfurt. As such, it requires a slightly different although related positioning to second-order observation: if the latter is the position which oscillates between positions, then critique entails a constant deferment of the concept and praxis of position. Critique is simultaneously a position (in the sense of distinction and self-positioning this or that side of the distinction) and a nonposition (in that it is already elsewhere, atopic and utopian, embracing the world conditions), and in that sense it can be described as actualised contingency. Let me explain this by returning to the concept of observation. For Luhmann, it is conceivable that the concept of critique is replaced by that of observation,44 as long as a parallel level of observation is posited that would further contextualise the object of observation. This added level of observation cannot be performed simply as a chain of observation of observation (in that sense, it does not constitute properly speaking a third-order45), nor as the usual total rejection of the object of observation (in the form of capitalism, the system or class). Rather, critical observation entails that a second-order observer observes in and through herself the conditions of possibility of second-order observation.46 In other words, in addition to observing how others observe (second-order), one would observe in parallel the context of this very second-order observation which necessarily includes and implies self-observation.47 To recall, teasingly in this context, Theodor Adorno, “the object opens itself … to a sense of the constellation in which it stands; the possibility of internal immersion requires externality.”48 This, surprisingly and improbably, constitutes critique for Luhmann: a reflection on the possibility of second-order observation, an immersion in a self-observation which,49 however, takes into account its locatedness in the embracing externality of the world as the sum of parameters that enable observation. Critique stands astride with “a foot in both camps”,50 observing in parallel observation and its conditions of possibility; immanence and exteriority; object and horizon.


Thus, a critique of the law, including legal theory, is both openness to the law and escape from it, an engagement both with its specificity and its ability to expose itself as precisely an object of critique. This means that the law is seen both in its immanence and its societal location, both in its claustrophobic paradoxes and its environmental presence.51 As Costas Douzinas and Adam Gearey announce (possibly a little too optimistically) “without the law, critique would not exist, and vice versa. If law finds its destiny in its contestation, critique is bound constantly to become law.”52 But not, one should add, as a negative correlative to the law. Critique is law’s contingency, indeed its actualised contingency that performs a crossing into law while at the same time withdrawing from it. Critique of the law is precisely the revelation of this legal paradox, and presupposes (while breeding) what Peter Goodrich has called the schizophrenia of the legal thinker,53 namely, loving and hating the law simultaneously, in an invisible crossing that reinstates the schizophrenic simultaneity with every gesture. Thus, the difference with Luhmann is that the latter posits all critique as self-observation. But this proves to be less straightforward than it may initially appear, and Luhmann clearly points to this difficulty and posits it as the main limitation of any (critical) observation. Observation is steeped into improbability, for the very conditions that enable observation are also the ones that hinder it: although observation takes place in the context of a perceived totality that includes the observer, it is this very inclusion that excludes the possibility of a total ‘worldly’ observation. One cannot observe oneself and the world simultaneously, for then where would the blind spot, the ‘back’ of the observer as it were, be located if not within the world? There is a positional modesty associated with it, an understanding of limitations that comes as a result of awareness of the partiality of observation, which renders all observation self-observation, all critique self-critique, and every horizon an inscription within the piazza.




Locating critique


But where can critique be located? Is the horizon, with its seductive escape routes and its utopian riddles, the place to seek critique? Phenomenologically, as the surface on which the various vanishing points converge, the horizon is correlative to the object that stands before it. Husserl speaks of the horizon as what is “not strictly perceived and yet is indeed there too.”54 The object that blocks the horizon, or at least its total horizontality, enables at the same time its emergence. Let me refer to those paintings again: galleries, trains, statues, all competing to block the vertiginous horizon while bringing forth chunks of it, fragmenting it into a multiplicity of potential parameters and angles. The beginning of the horizon originates in the echoing whispers of the piazza – for if there were no piazza, the horizon would have been merely sky. But, at the same time, the topological singularity, architectural arbitrariness and perspectival contingency of the piazza can only be described against the sheet of the horizon. As its etymology reveals, horizein is to separate and to delimit. This reciprocal limitation between object and horizon traces precisely the connection between observation and its conditions. Therefore, locating critique on either of those would be partial. This is, then, where – or perhaps more accurately how – critique is to be sought: in the oscillation between the two, and further the oscillation between positioning and non-positioning. It cannot espouse a unidirectional rejection, nor look entirely the other side if it wants to remain relevant to the object of critique. This does not of course mean that critique has to be sympathetic to its object. On the contrary, it would have to determine itself in connection to it but from an always parallel position. In turn, this position is correlative to the object of critique, but not unidirectionally determined by it. To recall Michel Foucault, critique is not the Kantian enquiry of the limit of knowledge, but a “reflecting upon limits”, a self-reflecting that reveals limits as limitations.55 The limit would have to be seen in its proper liminality as the distinction between inside and outside, which can only however be observed through another distinction. Thus, the Foucaultian critical quest for “whatever is singular, contingent, and the product of arbitrary constraints” is inscribed within the calculable space of the “universal, necessary, obligatory”56 but, as Julia Chryssostalis points out, looking out towards franchissement, crossing over, opening up.57


This opening up cannot be found in the Husserlian horizon. Its correlativity proves inadequate unless conceptualised as the brim on which improbability, unanticipated surprise and elusive contingency bubble. This means that the horizon retains its immanence as a limit, while insinuating exteriority as limitlessness. The horizon remains the limiting presence that augurs the absence of limit. In that sense, critique needs to withdraw from the horizon while retaining its horizontality. This is all the more relevant in view both of its potential co-optation by an all-blocking, all-thematising, colonising object, and because of what Jacques Derrida reminds us with regard to its temporality: “as its Greek name suggests, a horizon is both the opening and limit that defines an infinite progress or a period of waiting.”58 A horizon contains in its folds an inscription of anticipation and an anticipated inscription that seductively breeds the illusion of knowledge of the future. The horizon becomes the limit “from which I pre-comprehend the future. I wait for it. I predetermine it. And thus, I annul it.”59 Just as the infinity of the horizon is annulled and the surprise is contained through anticipation, in the same way the object of observation becomes emplaced, fixed, fully knowable and ultimately beyond critique. The critical observation loses its reflexive position of fragmenting embrace, and double vision becomes dust.


Yet we know from Heidegger that the horizon is also “the openness that surrounds us”,60 a direct spatialisation of the Husserlian temporality of protention and retention, namely the gestures towards the openness of the future and the past. This means that the horizon is not just a line but a nebulous circle swirling around whatever is located in its middle, in an embracing temporality that takes place in the present61 but folds into its actuality both future and past horizon. In its future monopoly, horizon burdens; but in its excursus into the past and its recovery of a spatiality that surrounds rather than simply stands in front, the horizon comes forth and recovers its infinite potential as the oscillation between two limits. A way of conceptualising such a spatiotemporal fusion is through the ambiguity of the word before:62 the horizon stands both before the object (the object always faces the horizon) and before the object (the horizon is always prior). ‘Before’ denotes, on the one hand, that something has come before me and indicates priority (has come before me in a generation, in a queue, in a bidding); and on the other, that something stands before me, in front of me, facing me, and to which I wish to arrive. Origin and destination, mother and desire, pathos and pothos: a uroborous flow of mutual paradoxification,63 a fate of claustrophobia in the cogs of return, an echo spanning Eden and End emerging before me while repeating ‘be for me!’ The horizon is always ‘before’, both prior and following. The revelation of the horizontal circularity in its translucent circumference as always ‘before’ me, leaves me running constantly between the two extremes while blind-spotting the destination, residing on what is already here yet moving away from it, never expecting what is to arrive, never limiting the surprise of improbability yet always moving towards elsewhere.


The defining feature of the horizon is not so much that it can never be reached; rather, it is the singular phenomenon that the further towards the horizon one goes, the larger expanse is swallowed up by one’s steps, and the larger the blind horizon behind one’s back. And ‘turning back’, as Luhmann says, “means that any pursuit of intentions or themes is always experienced as approaching, never as receding from, a horizon.”64 Turning back means at best turning towards an instrumentalisation of memory, and at worst, simply another horizon. Running towards the horizon is always just that, regardless whether one has ‘turned back’. So, how about if one went backwards without turning, started running away from the horizon in a frenzied attempt to see more, to begin waiting without waiting, to take a greater distance, to exclude more by engulfing more?65 What if one were to withdraw from the horizon without turning one’s back to it, take forward steps backwards as it were, thus eliminating any waiting since waiting would already be behind? In this very lack of sense, of direction, of meaning, the horizon is constructed as the negativity that cannot rely on mnemonic structures, careful planning or imagination in order to acquire its sense, direction or meaning. The emptiness of the oscillating surrounding horizons annul, neither the object nor future, but waiting itself. The horizon retains the universality of the conditions, the all-engulfing worldiness which demands to be seen when critique observes itself observing. At the same time, the universality remains inoperable, invisible, absent but for the trace of light on the line of the horizon.66


Critique is located on that very withdrawal from the horizon, while simultaneously keeping the horizon before its observing tirades. What this means for critique is that it can no longer posit a horizon in the sense of a ‘better’ place ‘outside’, and expect not to be disappointed with the galloping engulfing of whatever ‘outside’ has been imagined. One can, therefore, agree with Luhmann and reject the possibility of a better place outside society – provided, however, that in its stead, one finds a multiplicity of perspectives that offer immanent horizons as grounded gashes of escape. Indeed, this is the challenge for contemporary critique: to retain the suspicion of the outside, of the openness of unknowability, while operating within the limits traced precisely by this unknowability. Critique cannot target its future because then it plans it, anticipates it, colonises it. Critique cannot reside in the horizon because then critique can no longer oscillate between the open circularity of the horizon and the groundedness of its conditions, somewhere in the middle of which critique always meets itself and applies itself to itself. Finally, critique withdraws from the horizon while retaining its possibility, runs backwards towards yet another oscillation. It remains unlocatable, distant yet immersed, encompassing object and conditions of critique. Critique exerts itself in withdrawal, waits without waiting, flirts with utopia without reaching it, closes in on the object without managing to come close to it, in short: it never stops withdrawing, crossing, oscillating. Luhmann’s location of critique as the immersion in a self-observation that takes into account its locatedness in the embracing externality of the world as the sum of parameters that enable observation, can be understood in the above sense of withdrawal from, yet retention of, the horizon. This is the reason for which the horizon is not simply the openness or indeed the other side of the distinction to the piazza, but rather more modestly, the platform that enables distinctions and contextualises oscillations.


Lest one think, however, that Luhmann may be hinting at a readily available plausibility of critique, one should experience one of his famous cold showers or Unterkühlung [‘supercooling’]:67 “a constant oscillation … can be established only if there is time available to redirect emphases and if one already knows, even while being fascinated by phenomena, that one will regret this and ask oneself: Why does that interest me at all?”68 The question either opens up the possibility of arguing for a committed critique that extends itself over time and against all indications of lack of immediate benefit and of hope of actually controlling the way a difference may occur (and one readily thinks here of ecological problems); or it allows everything to collapse under the powerful discouragement of reflection over objects and conditions when faced by the temporality of the non-anticipated. But, as usual, Luhmann refrains from prescribing what one should do. He aspires to describe how things usually are, retaining often despite himself a slice of possibility for impossibility. And in that slice, the non-waiting of the critique is there for the taking as long as it is adequately contextualised in conditions of possibility. This is, therefore, the departure within description: to return to the original discussion on the difference between description and prescription, whereby the former retains itself and its object as destination, observation as critique departs from its position of observation, and it does so continuously. This is what I meant when I talked earlier about critique as actualised contingency: observation as critique is always unlocatable, in that as soon as one tries to locate it this or that side, critique withdraws, departs for the other side but in way that cannot be predicted, thus oscillating between position and non-position. If this means that society includes its critique, then so be it. But society can give no indication of direction (it includes all in actuality or potentiality), cannot legitimise one and not another critique, and does not encourage anticipation any more than a horizon from which one withdraws.69 The construction of critique as a withdrawing, ‘backwards’ stepping observation that cannot be located firmly through time and from which no ‘better’ other place is anticipated, is not necessarily conservatory, pro-status quo or politically ‘quiet’. On the contrary, it can be noisy and radical and eventually more constructive, because rather than a call to arms that typically excludes, targets and misses, it advocates a parallel observation of the conditions under which society is what it is, and a return to the point of departure, itself only one elusive stage in the process of continuous oscillation. With this, the utopian value of description is revealed: critique is a process of successful failure in the face of continuous disappointment. This may sound unduly pessimistic, but if one sees it, as I believe it should be seen, as the indefatigable continuation even in the face of failure tempered by what Luhmann dryly calls “the moderation of unnecessary excitement”,70 then one stands a better chance of being critical.


One last clarification: critique remains an observation and as every observation, it constructs for itself a standpoint from which other observers can be observed. In this sense, critique remains observable for other (critical) observers.71 In time, though, in the horizontality of the surrounding conditions, critique reflects on its own oscillation. It follows itself as it were without ever catching up. In this way, critique renders itself presently unobservable, not just for itself72 but significantly for others too: the standpoint of critique is never given but always already withdrawn for yet another point in the orbit of its oscillation. It can only be observed in its absence, in an empty room that carries a whiff of a just-now withdrawal. The meaning of this absence will be further elaborated in the course of the book, but at this stage it is relevant to mention that critique as absence is not the absence of critique; rather, it is the impossibility of fixing critique with a specific object and horizon without taking into consideration the unobservability of its performance. Luhmann’s description of critique should be understood as precisely the impossibility of one final separation, distinction, judgement, and as the inexhaustible oscillation between positions: “the oscillation itself, namely the necessity, when occupying one side of a form [i.e., the inoperable unity of two extremes, such as object and horizon here] to release the other side for reoccupation.”73 And the function of a functional critique is to sustain the possibility of the impossible through the improbability (all the more so because of continuous disappointment) of redirecting of emphases.74


In some ways, this book may be considered a redirecting of emphasis from a systemic presence to a critical absence. But it should quickly become clear that this redirection is only impressionistic. To start with, Luhmann’s texts perform a continuous oscillation between the two positions of position and of non-position. They redefine the concept and practice of critique as description, positing utopian journeys and mythical encounters,75 which however are always folded in the return to the object of description. Luhmann’s position remains unlocatable, as I show in the following section. As such, any redirection of emphasis has already been included within the texts themselves, leaving to the reader the choice of direction. On another level, however, a critical reading of Luhmann cannot concern itself with whether Luhmann is a critical thinker or not, nor can it assume normative standards from which the critique is to be performed. An autopoietic critical observation, namely an observation of the sort described above, is an oscillation between observing the way Luhmann observes and the conditions under which such an observation (that of observing Luhmann observing) is possible. In other words, a self-reflection on how it is that I observe Luhmann the way I do. In so doing, my location remains unobservable: well within the edifices of the piazza but also stepping onto the horizon, going backwards in order to engulf more and thus exclude more, departing from the point of departure, withdrawing from the side on which I can be located. I am not interested in speaking on the level of theory (wherever that is) or theories (in an attempt to grand the end of grand narratives); nor, however, am I talking on the level of empirical application. Rather, I am interested in constructing a translucent net of theoretical observations that will at times reveal things both smaller and larger than themselves. This may be more ‘knitting’ than writing, more superimposing loops of textual yarns than being intent on producing a ‘critical’ text – more poetics than polemics. To this some ‘unknitting’ is added, an unfolding of the knots in oscillating negativity that would always fail to correspond to a synthetic construction. Thus, I rely on the text to reveal the way I read Luhmann, inside out, playfully, frivolously. I accept that this may lead “only to an involution of architectonics without altering the foundations”: the basis on which an earlier Gunther Teubner scathingly dismissed system theorists who “decorate the facades of their autopoietic palaces with deconstructive fragments of différance, of iteration, of trace.”76 What I find myself unable to do, though, is distinguish between ‘foundations’ and ‘architectonics’, between ‘decoration’ and, what? ‘substance’? I also find myself unable to perceive ‘the’ ‘system’ the way most system theorists seem to perceive it (but I would argue, neither Luhmann nor Teubner anymore) and consequently to locate myself in the category of either systemic or unsystematic theorist. Finally, I find myself unable to attach the adverb ‘only’ to the noun ‘involution’. In other words, I would be satisfied if this text managed to do ‘only’ that. Because, really, this text sets out to do something even baser, almost debased. This text wants to cheat. The performativity of the text – the text observing itself and its possibility of observing whatever it observes including itself – is what I later explain as ‘cheating’.77 Cheating reflects both the mode of this book (which can be glibly, treacherously and indeed tautologically described as ‘critical autopoietic’, thus announcing beyond any doubt its cheating intentions through its adjectives); and (the way I read) Luhmann’s writing itself. At the same time, cheating operates on yet another level. To read Luhmann critically, and to read Luhmann-the-critical-thinker, are two sides of the same thing. But one has to play the game (indeed, the same game that Luhmann plays) and start from a critical reading of (a non-critical) Luhmann, only to reveal the other side: that Luhmann is a critical thinker. In that sense, I do not need to cheat; but I choose to do so, for cheating in this case actually turns out to be playing with the rules: thus, begin by accepting the difficulty of accepting Luhmann the critical thinker, and then, through the same rules revealing what the rules themselves cannot accommodate. Cheating is to have access both to the fleur-de-lis on the back of the cards and to the side reserved only for the other players. Cheating is playing with the rules while at the same time resisting honesty and having a sneaky look at how things could have been – not necessarily better, just contingent. This is what this book aims at.




The problem with Luhmann


Luhmann has been variously hailed as “the most noteworthy contemporary social theorist”,78 “the most important social theorist of the 20th century”,79 and even as the rather cooler “most productive theorist of society writing.”80 Statistics are supportive certainly of the last superlative: since 1968 and until his death in 1998, Luhmann produced more than fifty books and a vast number of smaller pieces of work outlining different sides, takes and applications of his theory. Only his books include a challenging array of areas, beginning with the publication in 1984 of his first major work Social Systems: The Outline of a General Theory,81 and carrying on with books on economy, science, love, religion, politics, art, media, law, semantics, risk and ecology, to the conceptual culmination of his endeavours in 1997 with his magnus opus Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft (‘The Society of Society’), which remains untranslated in English.82 Interestingly, there is a certain obsession in the secondary literature, especially the one appearing after his death, with mentioning the number of printed pages that Luhmann has produced during his 30 years of writing activity. This is less odd than it would originally seem, considering that most Anglophone articles on Luhmann feel the need to fill a horror vacui: in the English-speaking academia, Luhmann is a marginal figure. He may be in a constant state of up-and-comingness but he is never quite there. Flirtation with Luhmann is abundant, and a reference or two may even be de rigeur under certain conditions, but further engagement risks being a tad too engaged. There are several reasons for this, most of them adequately dealt with by others.83 Here I wish to deal briefly with a group of reasons that can be roughly put together under the term ‘cheating’ in the sense mentioned above.


Luhmann cheats all the time. His ‘cheating’ amounts to a sort of vanishing act. On a very technical level, he quite simply goes through the creative process of reading thoroughly and employing selectively a host of authors in order to construct his own theory. Footnotes are of course used extensively – but the ideas and methods employed are presented in such a way that one is encouraged to forget their original context and see them anew. But Luhmann’s cheating is not just the obliteration or at least relativisation of the original context; rather, this conceptual rebaptising never loses the original context from sight. It is a look on both sides, but so artfully done that the original remains present while fading into insignificance. Parsons, Weber, Durkheim, Kant, Hegel, Husserl, Heidegger, Spencer Brown, Darwin, Nietzsche, Maturana, Varela, Freud and Marx are at the same time pivotal portraits on Luhmann’s concept board and ghostly sketches. These thinkers have deeply (albeit variously) influenced Luhmann’s theoretical constructions, and remain (although again variously) present and potentially relevant for a better understanding of the theory. Yet, their appearance in Luhmann’s text is dissimulated in the form of either arbitrary groupings,84 oft-used mottos,85 or recondite methodological cameos that are not named, yet are clearly indebted. In this sense, however poignant and convincing criticisms may be that address Luhmann’s way of internalising and mis(using) other theories,86 they are misplaced.87 To start with, the goal behind this cheating is the production of a theoretical complexity which mirrors the social complexity that Luhmann observes in his writings. In some respects, Luhmann embarks upon a hyperreal production of societal function through his writings. More importantly though, criticisms of this sort miss the fundamental point of indifference of origin that Luhmann promotes both through his theory and performatively through his text. Just as autopoietic systems reproduce their outside within their boundaries in a way that no direct access or reference to this outside can be performed, in this very way Luhmann reproduces his theoretical environment in an autopoietic way on the level of his theory.88 Admittedly, the combination of loss yet recalling of origin through performative ingestion is disorienting. While, on the one hand, Luhmann does not sound like anything previously encountered, on the other hand he also sounds a bit like this or that – but never quite: Luhmann packs in a great deal of ‘uncanny’ in his writing, which is a direct result of the performativity of his writing.


Let me explain this by recourse to Luhmann’s fundamental rejection of what he calls “the ontological conception of the world.”89 For this, a brief digression to Husserl is required. The original Kantian move from an ontological, truth-oriented conception of the world to an epistemologically-mediated construction that attests to ‘how’ rather than ‘what’ and replaces the quest for identity with a quest for positionality, has been established in phenomenology with Husserl’s concept of intentionality,90 namely the reciprocal condition of constitution between consciousness and objects, or consciousness’s directedness towards specific objects: consciousness is always consciousness of something. Object and subject are linked with the bridge of intentionality which guarantees that neither can operate independently of the other, yet neither is reducible to the other. The chasm of Cartesian dualism is attempted to be bridged by the bracketing of objective reality, and the (not-always-so) subtle release of a solipsistic subjectivism, which communicates with the world through intentionality. Although Husserl admits that reality ‘in itself’ does exist, that objects do have an existence independent of a subject,91 an observer (or an agent