A World without Law Professors
HIS INTRODUCTORY chapter, Mark Van Hoecke identified a number of different approaches to legal research.1 The following chapter uses an alternative starting point in order to discuss the variety of legal research: I wonder what would be lost if law professors disappeared from the world. One purpose of this thought experiment is to identify for which type of legal research we really need legal academics, or whether legal scholarship could also become part of other social sciences or humanities. Moreover, it will be discussed how this relates to legal teaching and education: do we need law professors to train lawyers, or would it be feasible to separate education and research?
I. INTRODUCTION
In his book the The World Without Us, Alan Weisman examines how the world would react if humans suddenly vanished.2 In order to answer this question he starts with a look at the world before us. However, his analysis is not limited to it since the future of a world without us would not perfectly mirror the past. Moreover, he addresses the policy question of his scenario: ‘Is it possible that, instead of heaving a huge biological sigh of relief, the world without us would miss us?’3
Inspired by Alan Weisman’s book, this chapter will study the thought experiment of a world in which we extract not all human beings but ‘just’ law professors.4 The term ‘law professors’ needs further explanation. I will use it for every legal academic who teaches and researches at law schools/faculties in universities. It does not cover practitioners who are engaged in legal teaching and writing, or academics from other disciplines interested in law. Indeed, the two main parts of this chapter discuss whether the functions that in the current system are performed by law professors cannot also be performed by other persons or institutions.
II. LEGAL TRAINING AND EDUCATION
A world without law professors could be disastrous for legal training and education, and thus the legal and economic system as a whole. Although it is difficult to establish a causal relationship between law and economic development,7 the present chapter accepts that we need legal rules as well as lawyers with expertise in these rules.8 However, one could argue that legal education, or at least legal training, could also be provided by other institutions.
A. Legal Training by Other Institutions
The usefulness of university- or institution-based legal training has often been questioned. In the early twentieth century Thorstein Veblen asserted that ‘the law school belongs in the university no more than a school of fencing or dancing’.9 Also, at the end of the century, Juergen Ostertag compared theoretical legal education to the school of driving which attempted to teach people how to drive by teaching a detailed manual of the car and then allowing trainees to drive in traffic.10
At least for legal education, there are good reasons for this development. Due to the growing juridification of society, it cannot easily be assumed that prospective lawyers would learn everything they need to know ‘on the job’. Given the complexity of the legal system, an institution-based legal education can ensure that the knowledge and wisdom of the current generation of lawyers can be handed over to the next one.14 Historically, Frederick Pollock defended university-based legal education since it is a technical study ‘which cannot be undertaken here, or not so well here as elsewhere’.15 Thus, an apprentice system could provide a certain level of legal training but, even in a world without law professors, it would not be chosen as the sole means of transmitting legal knowledge.
Thus, a second, and more realistic, counter-model would be based on legal training in law schools whose teachers are not law professors or other academics. These law teachers would be practitioners who do some part-time teaching, or who teach full-time for a defined period of time. Some may argue that this cannot work. In 1887, the US-American jurist Christopher Columbus Langdell alleged:
If it [ie law] is not a science, it is a species of handicraft, and may be left by serving an apprenticeship to one who practises it. . . . If printed books are the ultimate sources of all legal knowledge, . . . then a university, and a university alone, can afford every possible facility for teaching and learning law.16
This Langedellian view of law as ‘law in books only’ was, however, already discredited by the US legal realists of the early twentieth century. Jerome Frank also proposed a major reform of teaching law students.17 Many law schools, he claimed, were not equipped to train lawyers but to graduate men able to become law teachers. Thus, they were not ‘lawyer-schools’ but ‘law-teacher schools’. Instead, he suggested a ‘clinical lawyer-school’ where a considerable proportion of law teachers should not have less than five to 10 years of varied experience in the actual practice of law.18
It may be argued that these suggestions may be working in the United States because, being post-graduate institutions, US law schools already have a vocational focus, whereas in the United Kingdom (and other European countries), law faculties provide general legal education.22 However, this difference should not be overemphasised. In the United Kingdom too, the main focus of legal education is on teaching students to become practicing lawyers.23 Moreover, it can be suggested that the United Kingdom is already on the path to a clinical lawyer-school. For the purpose of entry into professional training, it is regarded as equivalent to an LLB degree if a non-law graduate passes a one year Diploma course. Such a course is not only offered by universities but also professional schools, such as the College of Law and the BPP.24 In addition, the BPP has just started its own LLBs and LLMs programmes, mainly taught by practitioners.25
From a continental European perspective it may, however, be objected that the academic nature of the Civil Law tradition would rule out any legal training without the involvement of universities. In the Civil Law world the first law professors emerged in Northern Italy in the 12th century. When the Italian city states increased commerce and trade, there was a need to expand and improve the legal system. This was done by way of reception of the Corpus Juris Civilis, which, however, needed law professors to understand and categorise the content of these rules.26 This academic background can still be felt today. For instance, Pierre Legrand argues that there are major differences between Civil Law and Common Law countries. Whereas the Common Law is said to be inductive, pragmatic, fact-bound, and past-oriented, the Civil Law is deductive, logical and systematic, rule-bound, and future-oriented.27
Thus, in Civil Law countries too, practitioners would be able to provide legal training equivalent to the current university-based training. In reality, a significant involvement of practitioners in teaching already takes place in many Civil Law countries. In Italy and the Netherlands it is common that law professors also practice as advocates. In Germany it is even the case that 95 per cent of all undergraduate students receive the majority of their undergraduate legal training from practitioners. These persons, called Repetitoren, prepare students for the First Juridical Exam. Students use these training courses because university classes are typically very large and German law professors are not able to tutor individual students. Since in many German cities there is an oversupply of practicing lawyers, these lawyers offer tailor-made training courses on a commercial basis.29
First, this concerns the substance of teaching. Practicing lawyers would be less interested in the abstraction of legal rules (or even their ‘supercomplexity’30) than academic teachers. In contrast to academics, they would also put more emphasis on persuasion than on establishing the ‘correct answer’ to a particular legal question.31 This sounds like a shortcoming but it can also be seen in a more positive light. According to Oliver Wendell Holmes, ‘the business of a law school is not sufficiently described when you merely say that it is to teach law, or to make lawyers. It is to teach law in the grand manner, and to make great lawyers.’32 Holmes did not specify these terms in detail. Presumably, he meant that lawyers should not only know the law but also learn how to think and how to perform like a lawyer. In this respect, teaching by practitioners may be advantageous because it can lead to more complete lawyers.33
Second, the amount of legal training may change. Currently, the majority of UK undergraduate law students do not go on to practice law.34 Thus, a market for legal education, where law schools are entirely run by the professions, may reduce legal education. In addition, the present class of practitioners may decide to train fewer lawyers than under the current system in order to be sheltered from competition. However, this outcome is not unavoidable, because the Government (or competition authorities) may step in to prevent a commodification of legal training.35 For instance, it may decide to establish state-run professional law schools where practitioners are hired to teach law. Furthermore, even without law professors, universities may still provide deep legal education.
B. Deep Legal Education
It is often said that legal education should not only focus on teaching the legal rules to undergraduate students. In substance, legal education should be part of a liberal education. Thus, there should also be a training of ‘intelligence and sensibility’,36 of ‘moral experience’,37 of understanding law ‘marked by methodological and epistemological diversity’,38 and of the skills to encourage students ‘to think for themselves’.39 In the UK context, William Twining also suggested that university law schools should adopt a broader and more ambitious role than they have in the past. They should reach
This broader role, he argues, can only be fulfilled by a law school which is an academic institution devoted to the advancement of learning about law.41
In the scenario of a world without law professors, various points have to be distinguished: first, some of these additional functions can also be fulfilled by purely professional law schools. For instance, these law schools too can teach students ‘to think for themselves’ (it really depends on how legal topics are taught and not who teaches them). Practitioners would also be very well equipped to provide more general education on the law, may it be to other lawyers as continuing education or to the general public. This can also be shown in the context of transition economies. Lawyers from the West have provided legal education in order to facilitate the transition of former Communist countries to market economies.42 Academic lawyers, however, may often feel overburdened by the request to suggest rules that will be directly relevant to the practice of an unfamiliar legal system,43 whereas legal practitioners have more experience in applying the law into different socio-economic contexts.
Second, there are some subjects which cannot easily be taught by practitioners. For instance, many of the old ‘legal x’ and new ‘law and x’ topics are part of legal education.44 However, legal practitioners would usually not have the time or interest to teach topics such as legal philosophy, legal history, legal sociology, law and economics, law and finance, law and religion, etc. In a world without law professors this can be solved by shifting these topics to other schools or faculties of the university. This may require some reallocation of resources; however, it may not be unfeasible because disciplines such as philosophy, history, or economics already have an interest in the role of law in their own disciplinary context.45 Then, for instance, some of this law-in-context education may be made a prerequisite for a law degree. Or, in reversal to the current situation, academics from these schools and faculties may be invited to deliver guest lectures at the purely professional law schools.
C. Conclusion
Without academic teachers, legal training would shift back to the legal professions. Purely professional law schools would provide legal training for future lawyers. This is feasible in both Common Law and Civil Law jurisdictions. These professional law schools can also be involved in a more general provision of legal education. In addition, non-law faculties of universities can take responsibility for teaching on law-related subjects. This role of other parts of the university will also become apparent in the following section on legal research.
III. LEGAL RESEARCH AND WRITING
Without law professors, law would disappear as a separate academic discipline. Some may applaud such a development. In 1848 Julius von Kirchmann gave a controversial talk at a lawyers’ conference in Berlin in which he claimed legal research to be worthless because it did not aim to establish general truths but merely to support the current legal system.49 A similar criticism can also be found today. For instance, it is said that